Larregue’s Critique of Cofnas et al. (2017): A Rejoinder

Larregue’s Critique of Cofnas et al. (2017): A Rejoinder Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 https://doi.org/10.1007/s12108-018-9372-6 1 2 Nathan Cofnas & Noah Carl & Michael A. Woodley of Menie Published online: 12 March 2018 ## The Author(s) 2018 Abstract Data from the General Social Survey indicate that conservatives’ self- reported trust in scientists has steadily decreased since 1974. In Cofnas et al. (The American Sociologist, 2017), we suggested that this trend may have been partly driven by the increasing tendency of scientific institutions, and the representatives of such institutions, to distort social science for the sake of liberal activism. Larregue (The American Sociologist, 2017) makes three opposing arguments: (1) It is Bvery hard^ to establish the charge of bias, especially since we did Bnot state what [we] mean by ‘bias.’^ (2) We did not establish a causal relationship between scientists’ (alleged) liberal activism and conservatives’ distrust of science, and we ignored activism by conservative scientists. (3) We were wrong to advocate Baffirmative action^ for conservatives in academia. We address these arguments in turn: (1) Larregue does not engage with our main arguments that liberal bias exists in social science. (2) In recent years, prominent scientific organizations have, with great publicity, intervened in policy debates, always supporting the liberal side without exception. It is not unreasonable to assume that this would diminish conservatives’ trust in these organizations. Contra Larregue, in Cofnas et al. (The American Sociologist, 2017) we explicitly acknowledged that conser- vative scientists can also be biased. (3) We never advocated Baffirmative action^ for conservatives, and in fact we object to such a proposal. . . . Keywords Politics and science Trust in science Political polarization Political bias in science * Nathan Cofnas nathan.cofnas@balliol.ox.ac.uk Balliol College, Oxford OX1 3BJ, UK Nuffield College, Oxford, UK Center Leo Apostel for Interdisciplinary Studies, Vrije Universiteit Brussel, Brussels, Belgium Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 329 Introduction Based on data from the General Social Survey (GSS), Gauchat (2012) reports that American conservatives’ trust in science has fallen significantly since 1974. GSS interviewers preface their question about trust in science with the following: I am going to name some institutions in this country. As far as the people running these institutions are concerned, would you say you have a great deal of confi- dence, only some confidence, or hardly any confidence at all in them? The interviewer then asks respondents about Bthe Scientific Community.^ In 1974, 49% of self-identified conservatives responded with Ba great deal^ compared with 48% of liberals and 45% of moderates. Moderates started reporting less confidence in the late 70s and early 80s. Conservatives’ confidence dropped steadily, while liberals showed no discernible change. By 2010, 38% of conservatives, 40% of moderates, and 50% of liberals answered Ba great deal.^ In Cofnas et al. (2017), we suggested that declining conservative trust in scientists—or the leaders of scientific institutions—might be due to increasing liberal activism by scientific institutions. We provided several examples where prominent, mainstream scientific organi- zations or prominent members of the scientific community have misrepresented findings in science (e.g., in testimony to Congress or as amici curiae) to promote liberal causes. We cited evidence that conservatives have lost trust not in all scientists, but only in so-called Bimpact scientists,^ i.e., those whose work has policy implications (e.g., psychologists who study discrimination). Conservatives have greater trust than liberals in Bproduction scientists^ whose work does not have policy implications (e.g., agricultural scientists) (McCright et al. 2013). In Cofnas et al. (2017), we focused on activism in social science, which encompasses the paradigm Bimpact sciences^ (sociology and psychology) that have played a role in numerous political debates in the last few decades. Larregue (2017) makes three opposing arguments to our paper: (1) It is Bvery hard^ to establish the charge of bias, especially since we did Bnot state what [we] mean by ‘bias.’^ (2) We did not establish a causal relationship between scientists’ (alleged) liberal activism and conservatives’ distrust of science, and we ignored activism by conservative scientists. (3) We were wrong to advocate Baffirmative action^ for conservatives in academia. We address these arguments in turn: (1) Larregue does not engage with our main arguments that liberal bias exists in social science. (2) In recent years, prominent scientific organizations have, with great publicity, intervened in policy debates, always supporting the liberal side without exception. It is not unrea- sonable to assume that this would diminish conservatives’ trust in these organizations. Contra Larregue, in Cofnas et al. (2017) we explicitly acknowledged that conservative scientists can also be biased. (3) We never advocated Baffirmative action^ for conser- vatives, and in fact we object to such a proposal. Is There a Liberal Bias in Social Science? Citing Gross (2013), Larregue (2017) suggests that scholars in different fields have different views about the extent to which Bpolitics should influence teaching and research.^ Those in 330 Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 some disciplines, such as biology, tend to take an Bobjectivist stance,^ denying that politics should have any influence on research. Scholars in other disciplines, such as the humanities, are Bmuch more skeptical about professors’ capacity to keep politics at bay^ (i.e., they accept that researchers’ politics can legitimately influence their work). Larregue writes: As Neil Gross found in the interviews he conducted, Bsociology is best described as an epistemological hybrid, combining elements of objectivism and skepticism^ (Gross 2013, p. 190). Interestingly, sociologists were further fractally divided between two scientific poles: those closer to the humanities or activist camp, who shared the belief that objectivism is an illusion, and those who endorsed a more professional and positivistic stance, for whom sociology should try to attain objectivity. This latter epistemological position was dominant among the sociol- ogists interviewed by Gross: BFor most American sociologists, in other words, objectivity remains an ideal toward which they claim to strive, even as they recognize the impossibility of ever fully achieving it^ (Gross 2013, p. 200). This tends to contradict CCW’s [i.e., Cofnas et al.’s] claim that social scientists are consciously distorting their science to fit their agenda. There are a couple things to say about this. First, according to the source that Larregue himself seems to take as authoritative, the Bbest descri[ption]^ of sociology is that it is an Bepistemological hybrid^ that is only partly committed to Bobjectivism.^ This suggests that, at the very least, there is a major element within sociology that does not even try to Bkeep politics at bay.^ Second, Larregue cites Gross’s report that Bmost American sociologists^ that he (Gross) interviewed endorsed the objectivist stance. According to Larregue, BThis tends to contradict [our] claim that social scientists are consciously distorting their science to fit their agenda.^ But what does it mean for this to Bcontradict^ our claim? In light of the evidence we provided—i.e., examples of large numbers of social scientists acting collec- tively through their principal organizations to misrepresent science—how much probative value does Gross’s survey have? The fact that more than 50% of sociologists say in a survey that they are committed to objectivism does not, in our view, overturn strong evidence, based on their behavior, that they often distort science for political reasons. Larregue argues: To substantiate their claims, CCW use cherry-picked examples that, of course, confirm their hypothesis of a liberal bias in science. One major problem with CCW’s argument is that they do not clearly state what they mean by bias. Since we can envision more or less strict or lenient conceptions of what constitute a bias in science, their statement is quasi-irrefutable. The claim that we Bcherry-picked^ examples implies that there where comparable examples of both liberal and conservative bias, and we cited only examples of the former. So if we were guilty of cherry-picking, this would be very easy to demonstrate. Larregue simply needed to show several examples from the past few decades of a major, main- stream social science organization (such as the American Sociological Association or the American Psychological Association), or a recognized leader of a social scientific field (such as Robert Putnam), distorting science to advance a conservative political cause. But as far as we know not a single example of conservative bias like that exists at Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 331 all—Larregue certainly did not mention one. There may well be individual social scientists who are biased in favor of conservative-friendly interpretations of science, or right-wing think tanks that distort science. But these individuals and partisan think tanks have no influence over the major scientific organizations that represent the scientific establishment as a whole, and conservative mavericks are not regarded as leaders of their fields. Larregue is in a way correct when he says that we Bmix up different types of bias in the examples [we] use,^ such as Bfraud^ and Badvocacy.^ But we believe he draws an incorrect conclusion from this fact when he claims that this Bcontributes to blur [our] demonstration.^ Rather, our examples just show that mainstream social scientists engage in several different types of bias to advance liberal causes. The fact that some of our examples reveal multiple types of (liberal) bias operating simultaneously does not undermine our thesis that there is liberal bias in social science. Our thesis is not Bquasi-irrefutable^ because, to repeat, it would be refuted if Larregue could show examples of any type of bias employed by a mainstream social scientific organization to advance a conservative political cause. Larregue says that to Bsubstantiate^ our claims, we Brely on^ Inbar and Lammer’s (2012) Bsurvey of social and personality psychologists that showed liberal scientists willing to discriminate against their conservative colleagues.^ But, he says: When they come to the implications of their results, Yoel Inbar and Joris Lammers do not mention any sort of liberal bias that would distort research to fit political agendas. Their only statement regarding the content of science is that many aspects of conservative thinking can serve as inspiration for interesting research questions that would otherwise be missed (Inbar and Lammers 2012,p. 502). Apart from the fact that this is an unsubstantiated supposition, this argument by no means implies that liberal science is biased or wrong. Here again the authors confuse between the context of pursuit of research with the context of justification. Here Larregue is criticizing Inbar and Lammers’sargument—which we do not refer to at all—and portraying it as a criticism of our argument, which is different. As we will discuss more below, we do not necessarily believe that Bconservative thinking can serve as inspiration for interesting research questions that would otherwise be missed.^ But we do suggest that Inbar and Lammers’s findings reflect the existence of a liberal establishment in social science that seeks to suppress ideas that are not friendly to liberal politics. If a large percentage of personality and social psychologists admit that they would be inclined to reject conservative-friendly papers in peer review, to not invite a known political conservative to a symposium, and to reject conservative grant applications and job applications, this would contribute to an environment that is not receptive to liberal-undermining ideas, even if those ideas are sometimes correct. The Causal Link Between Scientists’ Liberal Activism and Conservatives’ Distrust, and the Issue of Conservative Activism Measuring Activism Larregue raises the problem of how we can show a causal relationship between increasing activism among scientists and conservatives’ distrust. How can we measure 332 Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 an increase in activism? BWhat variables can account for scientists’ social activism over time? CCW give no answer to these questions. They give examples of what they interpret as political activism, sure, but this does not prove a statistical increase.^ It is true that activism among scientists is difficult to measure. There is no uncon- troversial way to count up instances of activism among scientists, and measure a quantitative increase over the last four decades. However, just because we cannot investigate this question using ideal quantitative methods does not mean that the question cannot be approached in a reasonably systematic and scientific way. A great deal of historical analysis faces the same methodological problem. We can only point to numerous examples where scientists appear to have engaged in liberal activism in recent years. Since neither Larregue nor anyone else has been able to give comparable examples of conservative activism among scientists in the past few decades, we think it is reasonable to conclude that there is a trend toward more liberal activism. It is difficult to prove that there is a causal link between increasing liberal activism and conservative distrust in science. But we think it is a reasonable explanation for decreasing conservative trust in social science that, in the course of practically all major political debates, representatives of the social science community make an appearance to promote research that supports the liberal side. Whether it’s gun control, death penalty cases, affirmative action, or anything else, the ASA or the APA or the American Political Science Association—or sometimes all these organizations together—will testify to congress or submit amicus curiae briefs arguing that Bscience^ shows that the liberals are right. It seems the onus is on the critic to show why this wouldn’t decrease conservatives’ trust in social science. Did We Ignore Conservative Bias? Larregue claims that BAs conservative apostles of objectivity, CCW believe that liberal scientists are necessarily biased. Conversely, the mere possibility that conservative thinkers might be, too, biased, is not even mentioned.^ This is false. In Cofnas et al. (2017), we say, based on Honeycutt and Freberg’s(2017) findings, that BThe same proportion of conservatives and liberals [in academia] expressed willingness to dis- criminate against those with opposing political views.^ We calculated that about 1.33% of personality and social psychologists are conservatives who would acknowledge that they would discriminate against liberals. We then noted that a journal submission that goes through an editor and three referees would have a 5% chance of being handled by a conservative who discriminates against liberals. So we clearly acknowledged that conservatives can be biased, and we portrayed this as a problem. Larregue repeatedly accuses us of failing to recognize the difference between the Bcontext of discovery^ and the Bcontext of justification,^ because we supposedly assume that if scientists undertake scientific investigation with a liberal agenda then their results must be false. Larregue notes that it is possible to be motivated by bias but make legitimate discoveries. Ironically, however, it is Larregue who repeatedly confuses the contexts of discovery and justification in his criticisms of us and of conservatives. For example, he says: CCW also fail to take into consideration conservative scientists’ activism....In intelligence and race research, conservative scientists, from Arthur Jensen to Richard Herrnstein and Charles Murray (authors of The Bell Curve), were partly Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 333 financed by the Pioneer fund, a conservative organization that was active in the American eugenic movement (Kühl 2002). First of all, Richard Herrnstein and Charles Murray never received funding from the Pioneer Fund. (They were criticized for citing people who had received such funding.) More important, the fact that science is funded by an organization with a political agenda does not mean that the funded science itself is ipso facto Bactivism.^ In Cofnas et al., we never claimed that liberal scientists engaged in activism simply because they received funding from liberal organizations. The question is whether prominent, mainstream scientists and scientific organizations actively distort science to advance a political agenda. That is what we provided evidence for. Larregue also attempts to discredit us by claiming that we—Cofnas, Carl, and Woodley of Menie—are motivated to criticize liberal bias in social science by our conservative agenda to Badvance the position of conservative scientists within academia.^ Besides the fact that this is an illegitimate criticism because it conflates the contexts of discovery and justification, the evidence that Larregue brings forward to prove our commitment to a conservative agenda is problematic—even, we might say, biased. For example, he says: The lead author, Nathan Cofnas, has published op-eds in conservative outlets, including National Review and Quillette. Recently, he accused Stephen Hawking of promoting a BDadaist science^, after the world-renowned physicist said that Trump’s decision to withdraw from the Paris climate accord would Bpush the Earth over the brink.^ This is inaccurate. Cofnas (2017) criticized Hawking for his claim that Trump’s withdrawal from the Paris climate accord would Bpush the Earth over the brink to become like Venus, with a temperature of two hundred and fifty degrees [Celsius], and raining sulphuric acid.^ As a Google search of that quote will reveal, Hawking was widely criticized by mainstream climate scientists for expressing a view that had no justification whatsoever. Larregue accuses Noah Carl of having a conservative agenda because he Bhas contributed to the conservative academic blog Heterodox Academy.^ The fact that Larregue sees Heterodox Academy as Bconservative^ is rather illustrative, given that the organization is nonpartisan in both its mission statement and the composition of its members. As of June 26, 2017, Heterodox Academy’s members identified as Left/Progressive (18.2%), Right/Conservative (17.3%), Centrist/Moderate (24.9%), Libertarian/Classical Liberal (23.2%). (16.4% were unclassifiable, preferred not to say, or were Bother.^). Regarding Woodley of Menie’s supposed bias, Larregue says: BMichael A. Woodley of Menie...has given an interview about human intelligence to Stefan Molyneux, a well-known Canadian conservative podcaster who supported Trump's campaign.^ But Molyneux has conducted interviews on human intelligence with outspoken liberals including Eric Turkheimer and James Flynn. The fact that Molyneux interviewed someone does not indicate that he is a conservative, let alone that he has a conservative bias. The results of this survey can be found on Heterodox Academy’s website (http://heterodoxacademy. org/krugman-is-wrong-we-are-not-conservative/). 334 Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 Should There Be BAffirmative Action^ for Conservatives in Social Science? As discussed, Larregue devotes one-out-of-three of the main sections of his paper to criticizing us for advocating affirmative action for conservatives. He says: BThe third section of this article is devoted to CCW’s political proposal, namely introducing ‘affirmative action’ for conservatives in academia.^ Note the quotes he puts around the phrase Baffirmative action,^ which makes it seem that he is quoting us. However, the words Baffirmative action^ do not appear anywhere in Cofnas et al. (2017). We suspect that Larregue misinterpreted the last paragraph of our paper: In the past few years, a number of social scientists, led by Jonathan Haidt, have called upon social scientists to diversify the field and make a conscious effort to root out liberal bias (Duarte et al. 2015). We conclude with a prediction: If social scientists begin counteracting liberal activism, the trend of lowering conservative trust in scientists will reverse. (Cofnas et al. 2017) In this paragraph, we refer to the fact that Haidt endorses active efforts to recruit conservatives to social science, but we do not endorse this proposal. In fact we do not think it is a good idea. Our personal hope is that scientists, whether they are liberal or conservative, will stop being biased and discrimi- nating against others for political reasons. If this happens, we think more conservatives will become social scientists because it will be much easier for them to be hired and to pursue research that may not support liberal assump- tions about how the world works. Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and repro- duction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. References Cofnas, N. (2017). Dadaist science. The Weekly Standard. Retrieved from http://www. weeklystandard.com/dadaist-science/article/2008803. Accessed Feb 1, 2018. Cofnas, N., Carl, N., & Woodley of Menie, M. A. (2017). Does activism in social science explain conservatives’ distrust of scientists? The American Sociologist. 1–14 Advance online publica- tion. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12108-017-9362-0. Duarte, J. L., Crawford, J. T., Stern, C., Haidt, J., Jussim, L., & Tetlock, P. E. (2015). Political diversity will improve social psychological science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 38,1–13. Gauchat, G. (2012). Politicization of science in the public sphere: a study of public trust in the United States, 1974 to 2010. American Sociological Review, 77(2), 167–187. Gross, N. (2013). Why are professors liberal and why do conservatives care? Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Honeycutt, N., & Freberg, L. (2017). The liberal and conservative experience across academic disciplines: an extension of Inbar and Lammers. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 8(2), 115–123. Inbar, Y., & Lammers, J. (2012). Political diversity in social and personality psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7(5), 496–503. Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 335 Kühl,S.(2002). The Nazi connection: Eugenics, American racism, and German National Socialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Larregue, J. (2017). Conservative apostles of objectivity and the myth of a Bliberal bias^ in science. The American Sociologist.1–16 Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12108-017-9366-9. McCright, A. M., Dentzman, K., Charters, M., & Dietz, T. (2013). The influence of political ideology on trust in science. Environmental Research Letters, 8(4), 1–9. http://www.deepdyve.com/assets/images/DeepDyve-Logo-lg.png The American Sociologist Springer Journals

Larregue’s Critique of Cofnas et al. (2017): A Rejoinder

Free
8 pages
Loading next page...
 
/lp/springer_journal/larregue-s-critique-of-cofnas-et-al-2017-a-rejoinder-uX3uLbnyuz
Publisher
Springer US
Copyright
Copyright © 2018 by The Author(s)
Subject
Social Sciences; Sociology, general; Social Sciences, general
ISSN
0003-1232
eISSN
1936-4784
D.O.I.
10.1007/s12108-018-9372-6
Publisher site
See Article on Publisher Site

Abstract

Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 https://doi.org/10.1007/s12108-018-9372-6 1 2 Nathan Cofnas & Noah Carl & Michael A. Woodley of Menie Published online: 12 March 2018 ## The Author(s) 2018 Abstract Data from the General Social Survey indicate that conservatives’ self- reported trust in scientists has steadily decreased since 1974. In Cofnas et al. (The American Sociologist, 2017), we suggested that this trend may have been partly driven by the increasing tendency of scientific institutions, and the representatives of such institutions, to distort social science for the sake of liberal activism. Larregue (The American Sociologist, 2017) makes three opposing arguments: (1) It is Bvery hard^ to establish the charge of bias, especially since we did Bnot state what [we] mean by ‘bias.’^ (2) We did not establish a causal relationship between scientists’ (alleged) liberal activism and conservatives’ distrust of science, and we ignored activism by conservative scientists. (3) We were wrong to advocate Baffirmative action^ for conservatives in academia. We address these arguments in turn: (1) Larregue does not engage with our main arguments that liberal bias exists in social science. (2) In recent years, prominent scientific organizations have, with great publicity, intervened in policy debates, always supporting the liberal side without exception. It is not unreasonable to assume that this would diminish conservatives’ trust in these organizations. Contra Larregue, in Cofnas et al. (The American Sociologist, 2017) we explicitly acknowledged that conser- vative scientists can also be biased. (3) We never advocated Baffirmative action^ for conservatives, and in fact we object to such a proposal. . . . Keywords Politics and science Trust in science Political polarization Political bias in science * Nathan Cofnas nathan.cofnas@balliol.ox.ac.uk Balliol College, Oxford OX1 3BJ, UK Nuffield College, Oxford, UK Center Leo Apostel for Interdisciplinary Studies, Vrije Universiteit Brussel, Brussels, Belgium Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 329 Introduction Based on data from the General Social Survey (GSS), Gauchat (2012) reports that American conservatives’ trust in science has fallen significantly since 1974. GSS interviewers preface their question about trust in science with the following: I am going to name some institutions in this country. As far as the people running these institutions are concerned, would you say you have a great deal of confi- dence, only some confidence, or hardly any confidence at all in them? The interviewer then asks respondents about Bthe Scientific Community.^ In 1974, 49% of self-identified conservatives responded with Ba great deal^ compared with 48% of liberals and 45% of moderates. Moderates started reporting less confidence in the late 70s and early 80s. Conservatives’ confidence dropped steadily, while liberals showed no discernible change. By 2010, 38% of conservatives, 40% of moderates, and 50% of liberals answered Ba great deal.^ In Cofnas et al. (2017), we suggested that declining conservative trust in scientists—or the leaders of scientific institutions—might be due to increasing liberal activism by scientific institutions. We provided several examples where prominent, mainstream scientific organi- zations or prominent members of the scientific community have misrepresented findings in science (e.g., in testimony to Congress or as amici curiae) to promote liberal causes. We cited evidence that conservatives have lost trust not in all scientists, but only in so-called Bimpact scientists,^ i.e., those whose work has policy implications (e.g., psychologists who study discrimination). Conservatives have greater trust than liberals in Bproduction scientists^ whose work does not have policy implications (e.g., agricultural scientists) (McCright et al. 2013). In Cofnas et al. (2017), we focused on activism in social science, which encompasses the paradigm Bimpact sciences^ (sociology and psychology) that have played a role in numerous political debates in the last few decades. Larregue (2017) makes three opposing arguments to our paper: (1) It is Bvery hard^ to establish the charge of bias, especially since we did Bnot state what [we] mean by ‘bias.’^ (2) We did not establish a causal relationship between scientists’ (alleged) liberal activism and conservatives’ distrust of science, and we ignored activism by conservative scientists. (3) We were wrong to advocate Baffirmative action^ for conservatives in academia. We address these arguments in turn: (1) Larregue does not engage with our main arguments that liberal bias exists in social science. (2) In recent years, prominent scientific organizations have, with great publicity, intervened in policy debates, always supporting the liberal side without exception. It is not unrea- sonable to assume that this would diminish conservatives’ trust in these organizations. Contra Larregue, in Cofnas et al. (2017) we explicitly acknowledged that conservative scientists can also be biased. (3) We never advocated Baffirmative action^ for conser- vatives, and in fact we object to such a proposal. Is There a Liberal Bias in Social Science? Citing Gross (2013), Larregue (2017) suggests that scholars in different fields have different views about the extent to which Bpolitics should influence teaching and research.^ Those in 330 Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 some disciplines, such as biology, tend to take an Bobjectivist stance,^ denying that politics should have any influence on research. Scholars in other disciplines, such as the humanities, are Bmuch more skeptical about professors’ capacity to keep politics at bay^ (i.e., they accept that researchers’ politics can legitimately influence their work). Larregue writes: As Neil Gross found in the interviews he conducted, Bsociology is best described as an epistemological hybrid, combining elements of objectivism and skepticism^ (Gross 2013, p. 190). Interestingly, sociologists were further fractally divided between two scientific poles: those closer to the humanities or activist camp, who shared the belief that objectivism is an illusion, and those who endorsed a more professional and positivistic stance, for whom sociology should try to attain objectivity. This latter epistemological position was dominant among the sociol- ogists interviewed by Gross: BFor most American sociologists, in other words, objectivity remains an ideal toward which they claim to strive, even as they recognize the impossibility of ever fully achieving it^ (Gross 2013, p. 200). This tends to contradict CCW’s [i.e., Cofnas et al.’s] claim that social scientists are consciously distorting their science to fit their agenda. There are a couple things to say about this. First, according to the source that Larregue himself seems to take as authoritative, the Bbest descri[ption]^ of sociology is that it is an Bepistemological hybrid^ that is only partly committed to Bobjectivism.^ This suggests that, at the very least, there is a major element within sociology that does not even try to Bkeep politics at bay.^ Second, Larregue cites Gross’s report that Bmost American sociologists^ that he (Gross) interviewed endorsed the objectivist stance. According to Larregue, BThis tends to contradict [our] claim that social scientists are consciously distorting their science to fit their agenda.^ But what does it mean for this to Bcontradict^ our claim? In light of the evidence we provided—i.e., examples of large numbers of social scientists acting collec- tively through their principal organizations to misrepresent science—how much probative value does Gross’s survey have? The fact that more than 50% of sociologists say in a survey that they are committed to objectivism does not, in our view, overturn strong evidence, based on their behavior, that they often distort science for political reasons. Larregue argues: To substantiate their claims, CCW use cherry-picked examples that, of course, confirm their hypothesis of a liberal bias in science. One major problem with CCW’s argument is that they do not clearly state what they mean by bias. Since we can envision more or less strict or lenient conceptions of what constitute a bias in science, their statement is quasi-irrefutable. The claim that we Bcherry-picked^ examples implies that there where comparable examples of both liberal and conservative bias, and we cited only examples of the former. So if we were guilty of cherry-picking, this would be very easy to demonstrate. Larregue simply needed to show several examples from the past few decades of a major, main- stream social science organization (such as the American Sociological Association or the American Psychological Association), or a recognized leader of a social scientific field (such as Robert Putnam), distorting science to advance a conservative political cause. But as far as we know not a single example of conservative bias like that exists at Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 331 all—Larregue certainly did not mention one. There may well be individual social scientists who are biased in favor of conservative-friendly interpretations of science, or right-wing think tanks that distort science. But these individuals and partisan think tanks have no influence over the major scientific organizations that represent the scientific establishment as a whole, and conservative mavericks are not regarded as leaders of their fields. Larregue is in a way correct when he says that we Bmix up different types of bias in the examples [we] use,^ such as Bfraud^ and Badvocacy.^ But we believe he draws an incorrect conclusion from this fact when he claims that this Bcontributes to blur [our] demonstration.^ Rather, our examples just show that mainstream social scientists engage in several different types of bias to advance liberal causes. The fact that some of our examples reveal multiple types of (liberal) bias operating simultaneously does not undermine our thesis that there is liberal bias in social science. Our thesis is not Bquasi-irrefutable^ because, to repeat, it would be refuted if Larregue could show examples of any type of bias employed by a mainstream social scientific organization to advance a conservative political cause. Larregue says that to Bsubstantiate^ our claims, we Brely on^ Inbar and Lammer’s (2012) Bsurvey of social and personality psychologists that showed liberal scientists willing to discriminate against their conservative colleagues.^ But, he says: When they come to the implications of their results, Yoel Inbar and Joris Lammers do not mention any sort of liberal bias that would distort research to fit political agendas. Their only statement regarding the content of science is that many aspects of conservative thinking can serve as inspiration for interesting research questions that would otherwise be missed (Inbar and Lammers 2012,p. 502). Apart from the fact that this is an unsubstantiated supposition, this argument by no means implies that liberal science is biased or wrong. Here again the authors confuse between the context of pursuit of research with the context of justification. Here Larregue is criticizing Inbar and Lammers’sargument—which we do not refer to at all—and portraying it as a criticism of our argument, which is different. As we will discuss more below, we do not necessarily believe that Bconservative thinking can serve as inspiration for interesting research questions that would otherwise be missed.^ But we do suggest that Inbar and Lammers’s findings reflect the existence of a liberal establishment in social science that seeks to suppress ideas that are not friendly to liberal politics. If a large percentage of personality and social psychologists admit that they would be inclined to reject conservative-friendly papers in peer review, to not invite a known political conservative to a symposium, and to reject conservative grant applications and job applications, this would contribute to an environment that is not receptive to liberal-undermining ideas, even if those ideas are sometimes correct. The Causal Link Between Scientists’ Liberal Activism and Conservatives’ Distrust, and the Issue of Conservative Activism Measuring Activism Larregue raises the problem of how we can show a causal relationship between increasing activism among scientists and conservatives’ distrust. How can we measure 332 Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 an increase in activism? BWhat variables can account for scientists’ social activism over time? CCW give no answer to these questions. They give examples of what they interpret as political activism, sure, but this does not prove a statistical increase.^ It is true that activism among scientists is difficult to measure. There is no uncon- troversial way to count up instances of activism among scientists, and measure a quantitative increase over the last four decades. However, just because we cannot investigate this question using ideal quantitative methods does not mean that the question cannot be approached in a reasonably systematic and scientific way. A great deal of historical analysis faces the same methodological problem. We can only point to numerous examples where scientists appear to have engaged in liberal activism in recent years. Since neither Larregue nor anyone else has been able to give comparable examples of conservative activism among scientists in the past few decades, we think it is reasonable to conclude that there is a trend toward more liberal activism. It is difficult to prove that there is a causal link between increasing liberal activism and conservative distrust in science. But we think it is a reasonable explanation for decreasing conservative trust in social science that, in the course of practically all major political debates, representatives of the social science community make an appearance to promote research that supports the liberal side. Whether it’s gun control, death penalty cases, affirmative action, or anything else, the ASA or the APA or the American Political Science Association—or sometimes all these organizations together—will testify to congress or submit amicus curiae briefs arguing that Bscience^ shows that the liberals are right. It seems the onus is on the critic to show why this wouldn’t decrease conservatives’ trust in social science. Did We Ignore Conservative Bias? Larregue claims that BAs conservative apostles of objectivity, CCW believe that liberal scientists are necessarily biased. Conversely, the mere possibility that conservative thinkers might be, too, biased, is not even mentioned.^ This is false. In Cofnas et al. (2017), we say, based on Honeycutt and Freberg’s(2017) findings, that BThe same proportion of conservatives and liberals [in academia] expressed willingness to dis- criminate against those with opposing political views.^ We calculated that about 1.33% of personality and social psychologists are conservatives who would acknowledge that they would discriminate against liberals. We then noted that a journal submission that goes through an editor and three referees would have a 5% chance of being handled by a conservative who discriminates against liberals. So we clearly acknowledged that conservatives can be biased, and we portrayed this as a problem. Larregue repeatedly accuses us of failing to recognize the difference between the Bcontext of discovery^ and the Bcontext of justification,^ because we supposedly assume that if scientists undertake scientific investigation with a liberal agenda then their results must be false. Larregue notes that it is possible to be motivated by bias but make legitimate discoveries. Ironically, however, it is Larregue who repeatedly confuses the contexts of discovery and justification in his criticisms of us and of conservatives. For example, he says: CCW also fail to take into consideration conservative scientists’ activism....In intelligence and race research, conservative scientists, from Arthur Jensen to Richard Herrnstein and Charles Murray (authors of The Bell Curve), were partly Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 333 financed by the Pioneer fund, a conservative organization that was active in the American eugenic movement (Kühl 2002). First of all, Richard Herrnstein and Charles Murray never received funding from the Pioneer Fund. (They were criticized for citing people who had received such funding.) More important, the fact that science is funded by an organization with a political agenda does not mean that the funded science itself is ipso facto Bactivism.^ In Cofnas et al., we never claimed that liberal scientists engaged in activism simply because they received funding from liberal organizations. The question is whether prominent, mainstream scientists and scientific organizations actively distort science to advance a political agenda. That is what we provided evidence for. Larregue also attempts to discredit us by claiming that we—Cofnas, Carl, and Woodley of Menie—are motivated to criticize liberal bias in social science by our conservative agenda to Badvance the position of conservative scientists within academia.^ Besides the fact that this is an illegitimate criticism because it conflates the contexts of discovery and justification, the evidence that Larregue brings forward to prove our commitment to a conservative agenda is problematic—even, we might say, biased. For example, he says: The lead author, Nathan Cofnas, has published op-eds in conservative outlets, including National Review and Quillette. Recently, he accused Stephen Hawking of promoting a BDadaist science^, after the world-renowned physicist said that Trump’s decision to withdraw from the Paris climate accord would Bpush the Earth over the brink.^ This is inaccurate. Cofnas (2017) criticized Hawking for his claim that Trump’s withdrawal from the Paris climate accord would Bpush the Earth over the brink to become like Venus, with a temperature of two hundred and fifty degrees [Celsius], and raining sulphuric acid.^ As a Google search of that quote will reveal, Hawking was widely criticized by mainstream climate scientists for expressing a view that had no justification whatsoever. Larregue accuses Noah Carl of having a conservative agenda because he Bhas contributed to the conservative academic blog Heterodox Academy.^ The fact that Larregue sees Heterodox Academy as Bconservative^ is rather illustrative, given that the organization is nonpartisan in both its mission statement and the composition of its members. As of June 26, 2017, Heterodox Academy’s members identified as Left/Progressive (18.2%), Right/Conservative (17.3%), Centrist/Moderate (24.9%), Libertarian/Classical Liberal (23.2%). (16.4% were unclassifiable, preferred not to say, or were Bother.^). Regarding Woodley of Menie’s supposed bias, Larregue says: BMichael A. Woodley of Menie...has given an interview about human intelligence to Stefan Molyneux, a well-known Canadian conservative podcaster who supported Trump's campaign.^ But Molyneux has conducted interviews on human intelligence with outspoken liberals including Eric Turkheimer and James Flynn. The fact that Molyneux interviewed someone does not indicate that he is a conservative, let alone that he has a conservative bias. The results of this survey can be found on Heterodox Academy’s website (http://heterodoxacademy. org/krugman-is-wrong-we-are-not-conservative/). 334 Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 Should There Be BAffirmative Action^ for Conservatives in Social Science? As discussed, Larregue devotes one-out-of-three of the main sections of his paper to criticizing us for advocating affirmative action for conservatives. He says: BThe third section of this article is devoted to CCW’s political proposal, namely introducing ‘affirmative action’ for conservatives in academia.^ Note the quotes he puts around the phrase Baffirmative action,^ which makes it seem that he is quoting us. However, the words Baffirmative action^ do not appear anywhere in Cofnas et al. (2017). We suspect that Larregue misinterpreted the last paragraph of our paper: In the past few years, a number of social scientists, led by Jonathan Haidt, have called upon social scientists to diversify the field and make a conscious effort to root out liberal bias (Duarte et al. 2015). We conclude with a prediction: If social scientists begin counteracting liberal activism, the trend of lowering conservative trust in scientists will reverse. (Cofnas et al. 2017) In this paragraph, we refer to the fact that Haidt endorses active efforts to recruit conservatives to social science, but we do not endorse this proposal. In fact we do not think it is a good idea. Our personal hope is that scientists, whether they are liberal or conservative, will stop being biased and discrimi- nating against others for political reasons. If this happens, we think more conservatives will become social scientists because it will be much easier for them to be hired and to pursue research that may not support liberal assump- tions about how the world works. Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and repro- duction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. References Cofnas, N. (2017). Dadaist science. The Weekly Standard. Retrieved from http://www. weeklystandard.com/dadaist-science/article/2008803. Accessed Feb 1, 2018. Cofnas, N., Carl, N., & Woodley of Menie, M. A. (2017). Does activism in social science explain conservatives’ distrust of scientists? The American Sociologist. 1–14 Advance online publica- tion. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12108-017-9362-0. Duarte, J. L., Crawford, J. T., Stern, C., Haidt, J., Jussim, L., & Tetlock, P. E. (2015). Political diversity will improve social psychological science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 38,1–13. Gauchat, G. (2012). Politicization of science in the public sphere: a study of public trust in the United States, 1974 to 2010. American Sociological Review, 77(2), 167–187. Gross, N. (2013). Why are professors liberal and why do conservatives care? Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Honeycutt, N., & Freberg, L. (2017). The liberal and conservative experience across academic disciplines: an extension of Inbar and Lammers. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 8(2), 115–123. Inbar, Y., & Lammers, J. (2012). Political diversity in social and personality psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7(5), 496–503. Am Soc (2018) 49:328–335 335 Kühl,S.(2002). The Nazi connection: Eugenics, American racism, and German National Socialism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Larregue, J. (2017). Conservative apostles of objectivity and the myth of a Bliberal bias^ in science. The American Sociologist.1–16 Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12108-017-9366-9. McCright, A. M., Dentzman, K., Charters, M., & Dietz, T. (2013). The influence of political ideology on trust in science. Environmental Research Letters, 8(4), 1–9.

Journal

The American SociologistSpringer Journals

Published: Mar 12, 2018

References

You’re reading a free preview. Subscribe to read the entire article.


DeepDyve is your
personal research library

It’s your single place to instantly
discover and read the research
that matters to you.

Enjoy affordable access to
over 18 million articles from more than
15,000 peer-reviewed journals.

All for just $49/month

Explore the DeepDyve Library

Search

Query the DeepDyve database, plus search all of PubMed and Google Scholar seamlessly

Organize

Save any article or search result from DeepDyve, PubMed, and Google Scholar... all in one place.

Access

Get unlimited, online access to over 18 million full-text articles from more than 15,000 scientific journals.

Your journals are on DeepDyve

Read from thousands of the leading scholarly journals from SpringerNature, Elsevier, Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford University Press and more.

All the latest content is available, no embargo periods.

See the journals in your area

DeepDyve

Freelancer

DeepDyve

Pro

Price

FREE

$49/month
$360/year

Save searches from
Google Scholar,
PubMed

Create lists to
organize your research

Export lists, citations

Read DeepDyve articles

Abstract access only

Unlimited access to over
18 million full-text articles

Print

20 pages / month

PDF Discount

20% off