Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
Downloaded from http://read.dukeupress.edu/common-knowledge/article-pdf/27/1/108/867402/0270108.pdf by DEEPDYVE INC user on 30 March 2022 Irad Kimhi, Thinking and Being (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2018), 166 pp. A negative judgment (“S is not p”) says what is not the case, but since what is not the case is nothing and does not exist, a negative judgment says nothing and is not a judgment at all. Wittgenstein called this state of affairs “the mystery of nega - tion.” In making a negative judgment, I can be right in what I say even though I say nothing at all. No less fastidious a logician than Rudolf Carnap sneered at ph- i losophers who take such trie fl s seriously. Parmenides, the first of many who did, drew the conclusion that one simply cannot say or think what is not, admonishing followers: “Say and think only this, being is.” The challenge philosophers inherit from Parmenides is to explain an account of thought and being that liberates negation from its ontological prison and lets it loose into the world again. The price they usually pay for their explanation is metaphysical idealism. The truth of thinking (including thinking what is not) must depend on nothing but thinking itself, and the favorite way of explaining that proposition is to identify being with thought. If I think it, truly think it, then it is. This position is Kimhi’s, as well as that of Parmenides, Plotinus, and Hegel, though I find Kimhi too discreet about the idealistic quality of the philosophy he explains. To brutally summarize, the idea is that to think what is not is to think what is, with a self- consciousness of disagreement. There is no difference of content between S and not- S; the differ- ence lies entirely in the self- consciousness we bring to it. That sounds fine until we ask, What is this self- consciousness, and what is happening when one becomes self- aware of agreement or disagreement? Is that a natural activity like respira- tion or an evolved animal power like vision? Kimhi says the thinking in “ S thinks that p” is an activity sui generis, without analogy in living nature, a conclusion that is not available to anyone who takes Darwin seriously. He says nature does not include thinkers or thinking, which places human beings somewhere beyond nature. Nature is a whole, but not the whole of being. And beyond nature is . . . what? We have to use our imagination. So much onto- psychology just for a puzzle about negation? Why not naturalize logic, and truth too? Kimhi acknowledges resistance to the putative uniqueness of thinking, then sets it aside. He does not explain how his theory speaks to the reasons against idealism, rationalism, or androcentric human excep - tionalness. These are serious challenges to philosophical practice that should not be ignored, not even by logicians. — Barry Allen doi 10.1215/0961754X-8723117 C OM MO N K N O W L E D G E 10 8
Common Knowledge – Duke University Press
Published: Jan 1, 2021
You can share this free article with as many people as you like with the url below! We hope you enjoy this feature!
Read and print from thousands of top scholarly journals.
Already have an account? Log in
Bookmark this article. You can see your Bookmarks on your DeepDyve Library.
To save an article, log in first, or sign up for a DeepDyve account if you don’t already have one.
Copy and paste the desired citation format or use the link below to download a file formatted for EndNote
Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
All DeepDyve websites use cookies to improve your online experience. They were placed on your computer when you launched this website. You can change your cookie settings through your browser.