Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
When we discover the best way to do this, we will have discovered the best available account of reality. Obviously, the result will not be easy to explain to anyone who doesnât know what modern logic is. But I said that the technical character of Quineâs philosophy is only part of the difï¬culty that the obituary writers found in explaining the signiï¬cance of Quineâs contribution. Another part is that the writers (or the philosophers who advised them, perhaps) tried to âtone downâ Quineâs radical theses, and, in the process, not only distorted them but (worse) made them sound bland and uninteresting. The enormously controversial theses of âthe indeterminacy of translationâ and âontological relativityâ associated with Quineâs name were trivialized and made unrecognizable in the process. And this toning down reï¬ects, I think, a failure to see that there are two radically different sorts of philosophical genius. One sort of philosophical genius â Aristotle and Kant were, for their respective epochs, ideal exemplars â proposes a highly believable (at least in its own time), coherent, and profound account of reality and a profound criticism of the views of both forerunners and contemporary rivals. If one thinks that this is
Common Knowledge – Duke University Press
Published: Apr 1, 2002
Read and print from thousands of top scholarly journals.
Already have an account? Log in
Bookmark this article. You can see your Bookmarks on your DeepDyve Library.
To save an article, log in first, or sign up for a DeepDyve account if you don’t already have one.
Copy and paste the desired citation format or use the link below to download a file formatted for EndNote
Access the full text.
Sign up today, get DeepDyve free for 14 days.
All DeepDyve websites use cookies to improve your online experience. They were placed on your computer when you launched this website. You can change your cookie settings through your browser.