TY - JOUR AU - Virág, Gábor AB - Abstract We introduce learning into an otherwise standard two-sided search-and-bargaining market. There is uncertainty about the price distribution due to uncertainty about an underlying exogenous state of relative demand: in the high state, buyers are on the long side; otherwise, they are on the short side. In equilibrium, prices are on average higher in the high state. Individual agents learn about the distribution while searching. Agents typically start out by experimenting with a tough bargaining position—buyers may initially insist on a low price and sellers on a high price. After successive failures to trade, agents become increasingly pessimistic about the market conditions and soften their bargaining stance. When frictions are small, equilibrium transaction prices are approximately market clearing, despite aggregate demand being unknown. Thus, the search-and-bargaining procedure enables price discovery in a decentralized market. 1. Introduction Uncertainty about supply and demand is common, especially in decentralized markets. Labor markets, over-the-counter asset markets, and housing markets are examples where the market conditions may not be fully known to the market participants. This uncertainty has implications for agents’ behaviour: the agents may spend time experimenting with offers unlikely to be accepted, they may employ strategies to learn from market outcomes, and they may be more accommodating after being in the market for a longer time without trading. These patterns of experimentation, learning, and accommodation over time—while common in real-life markets—cannot be captured by search models in which the aggregate supply and demand conditions are known by the agents in the market. We introduce a model in which no individual trader knows the relative scarcity of the good being traded. Our model builds on standard frictional search-and-bargaining models in the tradition of Mortensen (1982). These models assume that the agents know the market conditions, while we assume that the agents do not. First, we analyse the trade and learning patterns that emerge under market-level uncertainty. Secondly, we ask whether the traders eventually learn the aggregate characteristics and whether the prices accurately reflect relative scarcity when the frictions are small. By studying those questions, we contribute to equilibrium search theory, a branch of the literature in which both sides of the market make strategic decisions. First, we construct a “full-trade” equilibrium. The identified equilibrium allows for a detailed analysis of trading strategies under market uncertainty in our model. We relate these strategies to the well-known winner’s curse and loser’s curse that feature prominently in auction theory. Secondly, we study the conditions under which the equilibrium price reflects market conditions; that is, conditions under which information is aggregated. The literature on dynamic matching and bargaining games, pioneered by Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1985) and Gale (1987), addresses the question of how prices are formed in decentralized markets and whether these prices are Walrasian. Existing models, however, assume that market demand and supply are common knowledge among traders. This assumption is restrictive because markets have been advocated over central planning precisely on the grounds of the markets’ supposed ability to “discover” the equilibrium prices by eliciting and aggregating information that is dispersed in the economy; see Hayek (1945). Beyond the theoretical importance, the question of whether markets aggregate information has implications for policies that are intended to increase the transparency of markets, to remove insider information, or to centralize markets to decrease informational frictions; see, for example, the discussion of benchmarks for increasing transparency in search markets in Duffie et al. (2016). The main policy implication of our work, however, is that decentralized markets may work reasonably well in achieving market clearance even in the presence of aggregate uncertainty, at least for small frictions. This was not immediately evident from existing work on decentralized markets, especially given negative results for related problems in the literature; see below. As an illustration of the setting we have in mind, consider a bidder on eBay who seeks to purchase a consumer good. eBay is a decentralized market but it still has a well-defined trading mechanism that is close to our model. When bidding on a particular item, a bidder shades her bid below her true valuation to account for the expected continuation value (waiting for another auction). Waiting costs give the current seller the market power to increase his reserve prices. Conventional search theory reflects these considerations. However, there is evidence that is not consistent with buyers knowing aggregate market conditions. Juda and Parkes (2006) study the eBay market for a specific Dell monitor. They find that “[a]mong the 508 bidders that won exactly one monitor and participated in multiple auctions, 201 (40$$\%$$) paid more than $$\$10$$ more than the closing price of another auction in which they bid, paying on average $$\$35$$ more (standard deviation $$\$21$$) than the closing price of the cheapest auction in which they bid but did not win” (emphasis in original). This piece of evidence shows not only that there is considerable price dispersion in that market but also that buyers do not always know the “going price” of the object. In fact, a bidder may later regret not having been more aggressive before. This is reflected in dynamic bid patterns as well: “A simple regression analysis shows that bidders tend to submit maximal bids to an auction that are $$\$1.22$$ higher after spending twice as much time in the system, as well as bids that are $$\$0.27$$ higher in each subsequent auction.” These observations are hard to reconcile with models of conventional search theory where buyers fully know market conditions from the outset.1 However, they are consistent with an environment with aggregate uncertainty where buyers need to learn the market conditions. We develop a model to study markets with aggregate uncertainty. The matching technology and the bargaining protocol are adopted from Satterthwaite and Shneyerov (2008). In every period, a continuum of buyers and sellers arrive at the market. All buyers are randomly matched to the sellers, resulting in a random number of buyers who are matched with each seller. Each seller conducts a first-price sealed-bid auction with a secret reserve price.2 Successful buyers and sellers leave the economy, and unsuccessful traders leave the market with some exogenous exit rate; otherwise, they remain in the market to be rematched in the next period. The exit rate acts similar to a discount factor: it makes waiting costly and is interpreted as the “friction” of trade. The defining feature of our model is uncertainty about a binary state of nature (high or low) similarly to Wolinsky (1990). The realized state is unknown to the traders and does not change over time. The state of nature determines the relative scarcity of the good. The mass of incoming buyers is larger in the high state and smaller in the low state, whereas the mass of incoming sellers is independent of the state of nature. The larger the mass of entering buyers relative to the mass of entering sellers, the scarcer the good. Every trader receives a noisy signal about the state of the world upon arrival. Moreover, at the end of the period, those who did not trade obtain additional information regarding the state because they draw an inference from the fact that their respective bids or reserve price is lost. Feedback is otherwise minimal: traders do not observe the reserve price or bids after the auction. We concentrate on steady-state equilibria that are monotone in the beliefs of the agents: a buyer who attaches a higher probability to the high state bids more, and a seller who attaches a higher probability to the high state sets a higher reserve price. We show that the buyers shade their bids to account for the opportunity cost of foregone continuation payoffs. Moreover, although the consumption value of the good is known, the fact that continuation payoffs depend on the unknown common state of nature makes the buyers’ preferences interdependent and introduces an endogenous common value element. The resulting winner’s curse leads to further bid shading: winning an auction implies that, on average, fewer bidders participate and that the participating bidders are more optimistic about their continuation payoff.3 Therefore, the winner’s curse implies a lower value for winning the good than was expected before winning. Offsetting the winner’s curse is the loser’s curse. The role of the loser’s curse for information aggregation in large double auctions was identified by Pesendorfer and Swinkels (1997). In our model, losing an auction implies that, on average, more bidders participate and that the participating bidders are more pessimistic about their continuation payoffs. The loser’s curse implies that bidders become more pessimistic and raise their bids after repeated losses over time.4 The behaviour of the sellers is quite different: after a seller has not been able to transact for a short period of time, he lowers his reserve price, believing that the state is most likely to be low. The reason for the quick concession is that the pivotal conditioning event (when calculating the winner’s curse effect) is the event when the largest bid is equal to a certain reserve price. Conditioning on this event tends to decrease the probability of the high state. An interesting illustration of this observation comes when we identify full-trade equilibria where the sellers accept all equilibrium bids. We are particularly interested in the equilibrium outcomes when the exogenous exit rate is small, which is interpreted as the frictionless limit of the decentralized market. We show that the limit outcome approximates the Walrasian outcome relative to the realized aggregate state of the market in many ways but not fully. First, we show that the equilibrium trading probabilities are competitive in the limit, that is, the short side of the market trades almost surely in the limit. Moreover, if the realized state is such that the mass of incoming buyers exceeds the mass of incoming sellers, the resulting limit price at which trade takes place is equal to the buyers’ willingness to pay, that is, the price is competitive in the limit. However, if in the low state the mass of incoming buyers is smaller than the mass of incoming sellers and vice versa in the high state, then the equilibrium price may be higher than the seller’s costs in the low state, that is, there are equilibria with non-competitive limits. We introduce an intuitive refinement, the refinement of monotone beliefs in Section 6. This refinement requires off-equilibrium beliefs to satisfy that a higher winning bid indicates that the state of the world is high with a larger probability. Under this refinement, we show that the equilibrium price is competitive in the limit even if sellers outnumber buyers. In Section 2, we discuss our contribution to the literature. In Section 3, we introduce the model. In Section 4, we introduce a class of full-trade equilibria. We show that such equilibria exist and use these equilibria to discuss and illustrate our main points. In Section 5, we characterize all equilibria for small frictions. In Section 6, we introduce the refinement of monotone beliefs and show that, with this refinement, all equilibria become competitive for small frictions. In Section 7, we provide a discussion of our other assumptions, applications, and policy implications. The Appendix contains the proofs of the characterization results from Sections 5 and 6. A Supplementary Online Appendix contains the proofs of all results about full-trade equilibria from Section 4. 2. Contribution to the Literature We contribute to research that studies the foundations for general equilibrium through the analysis of dynamic matching and bargaining games, which was initiated by Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1985) and Gale (1987).5 A central question is whether a fully specified “decentralized” trading institution leads to outcomes that are competitive when trade frictions are small. Well-known negative results by Diamond (1971) and Rubinstein and Wolinsky (1985) have demonstrated that this question is not trivial. In existing dynamic matching and bargaining models, market demand and supply are known. Thus, each market participant can individually compute the market-clearing price before trading. The absence of aggregate uncertainty is a substantial restriction for at least two reasons. First, assuming that all participants know the aggregate market conditions is unrealistic in many markets. Secondly, price discovery has been emphasized as an integral function of markets. Our model allows us to investigate whether and under which conditions decentralized markets can serve this function. There is a related strand of literature on consumer search, some of which considers uncertainty on the buyers’ side; see, for example, Benabou and Gertner (1993), Dana (1994), and Janssen and Shelegia (2015). Unlike in our model, in that literature, sellers know the state, and these contributions typically focus on “reserve-price equilibria” 6. In our model, no trader knows the state, we consider the full set of equilibria, and we study information aggregation with small frictions. Our work is also related to work on matching and bargaining with exogenously assumed common values.7 Particularly prominent contributions are Wolinsky (1990) and Blouin and Serrano (2001).8 These contributions provide negative convergence results and uncover a fundamental problem of information aggregation through search: as frictions vanish, traders can search and experiment at lower costs. This implies that traders increasingly insist on favourable terms, turning the search market into “a vast war of attrition” (Blouin and Serrano, 2001, p. 324). As a result, non-competitive prices can be sustained in Wolinsky (1990) and Blouin and Serrano (2001) even when search frictions are small.9 In our model, the winner’s curse implies a similar effect: when the exit rate vanishes, the buyers bid low for an increasingly large number of periods. Nevertheless, this “insistence problem” is overcome by the fact that agents who did not trade become more accommodating in subsequent meetings. Golosov et al. (2014) consider a related search model with common values in which the traded good is divisible and study the long-run outcome for fixed frictions. They do not study whether outcomes become competitive in the “frictionless” limit, and learning is qualitatively different with a divisible good. There is a large body of related work on the foundation for rational expectation equilibrium in centralized institutions.10 The assumption of a central price formation mechanism distinguishes this literature from dynamic matching and bargaining games in which prices are determined in a decentralized manner through bargaining. Finally, our work is related to the literature on social learning (Banerjee and Fudenberg, 2004), the recent work on information percolation in networks (Golub and Jackson, 2010), and information percolation with random matching (Duffie and Manso, 2007). In the latter model, agents who are matched observe each other’s information. In our model, learning from other traders is endogenous and depends on the chosen action (bid). 3. Model and Equilibrium 3.1. Set-up There are a continuum of buyers and sellers present in the market. In periods $$t\in \left\{...,-1,0,1,...\right\}$$, these traders exchange an indivisible, homogeneous good. Each buyer demands one unit, and the buyers have a common valuation $$v>0$$ for the good. Each seller has one unit to trade. The common cost of selling is $$c$$, with $$v>c\geq 0$$. Trading at price $$p$$ yields payoffs $$v-p$$ and $$p-c$$, respectively. A trader who exits the market without trading has a payoff of zero. Buyers and sellers maximize the expected payoffs. There are two states of nature, a high state and a low state $$\omega \in \{h,\ell \}$$. Both states are equally likely. The realized state of nature is fixed throughout and is unknown to the traders, similar to Wolinsky (1990). For each realization of the state of nature, we consider the corresponding steady-state outcome, indexed by $$\omega$$. The state of nature determines the constant and exogenous number of new traders who enter the market (the flow), and indirectly, the constant and endogenous number of traders in the market (the stock). The mass of buyers entering each period is $$d^{\ell }$$ in the low state and $$d^{h}$$ in the high state, with $$d^{h}>d^{\ell }>0$$. The mass of sellers who enter each period is the same in both states and is equal to $$s$$. There is uncertainty about who is on the long side of the market whenever $$d^{h}>s>d^{\ell }$$. The buyers and the sellers are characterized by their beliefs $$\theta \in \left[ 0,1\right]$$, the probability that they assign to the high state. (Sometimes $$\theta$$ is called a trader’s type.) Each buyer who enters the market privately observes a noisy signal $$x$$. The signal is distributed with support $$\left[ 0,1\right]$$ and with a cumulative distribution function (c.d.f.) $$G_{s}^{B}(x|\omega )$$ that admits a continuous density function, $$g_{s}^{B}(x|\omega )$$. The likelihood ratio $$\frac{g_{s}^{B}(x|h)}{g_{s}^{B}(x|\ell )}$$ is strictly increasing. Therefore, the Bayesian posterior $$\theta \left( x\right) =\frac{\left( 0.5\right) d^{h}g_{s}^{B}(x|h)}{\left( 0.5\right) d^{h}g_{s}^{B}(x|h)+\left( 0.5\right) d^{\ell }g_{s}^{B}(x|\ell )}$$ is strictly increasing in $$x$$ and, hence, invertible. We will work directly with the distribution of the induced posteriors to simplify the exposition later. The support of this distribution is $$[\underline{\theta }^{B},\bar{\theta}^{B}]=\left[ \theta \left( 0\right), \theta \left( 1\right) \right]$$. Its c.d.f. is $$G^{B}(\theta |\omega )=G_{s}^{B}(\theta ^{-1}\left( \theta \right) |\omega )$$, and its density is denoted $$g^{B}(\theta |\omega )$$.11 For a buyer, the mere fact of entering the market contains news because the inflow is larger in the high state. This is expressed by the likelihood ratio $$d^{h}/d^{\ell }>1$$.12 To avoid technical difficulties, and to simplify exposition, we assume that13   1/2<θ_B<θ¯B<1. (1) The sellers’ side is analogous. In state $$\omega$$, the induced posteriors of the entering sellers are distributed on the support $$[\underline{\theta }^{S},\bar{\theta}^{S}]$$ with $$0<\underline{\theta }^{S}<\bar{\theta}^{S}<1$$, with a c.d.f. $$G^{S}(\theta |\omega )$$ and density $$g^{S}(\theta |\omega )$$. Each period unfolds as follows: 1. Entry occurs (the “inflow”): A mass $$s$$ of sellers and a mass $$d^{\omega }$$ of buyers enter the market. The buyers and sellers privately observe signals, as previously described. 2. Each buyer in the market (the “stock” ) is randomly matched with one seller. A seller is matched with a random number of buyers. The probability that a seller is matched with $$n=0,1,2,...$$ buyers is Poisson distributed14 and is equal to $$e^{-\mu }\mu ^{n}/n!$$, where $$\mu (\omega )=D(\omega )/S(\omega )$$ is the endogenous ratio of the mass of buyers to the mass of sellers in the stock as described below. The expected number of buyers who are matched with each seller is equal to $$\mu (\omega )$$, of course. 3. Each seller runs a first-price sealed-bid auction with a secret reserve price $$r$$. Feedback is minimal: The buyers do not observe $$r$$ or how many other buyers are matched with the same seller. The bids are not revealed ex post, so a buyer learns only whether she has won, and a seller observes only whether the highest bid is above $$r$$. 4. A seller leaves the market if his good is sold; otherwise, the seller stays in the stock with probability $$\delta \in \lbrack 0,1)$$ to offer his good in the next period. A winning buyer pays her bid, obtains the good, and leaves the market. A losing buyer stays in the stock with probability $$\delta$$ and is matched with another seller in the next period. 5. Upon losing, the remaining traders who did not exit update their beliefs based on the information gained from losing with their submitted bids or not trading with their chosen reserve price $$r$$. Together with the inflow, these traders make up the stock for the next period. On the individual level, the exit rate $$1-\delta$$ acts similarly to a discount rate: Not trading today creates a risk of losing all trading opportunities with probability $$1-\delta$$. On the aggregate level, the exit rate ensures that a steady state exists for all strategy profiles. Traders do not discount future payoffs beyond the implicit discounting of the exit rate. We study steady-state equilibria in stationary strategies so that the distributions of the bids and reserve prices depend only on the state and not on time. An immediate consequence is that in any period, the set of optimal actions (bids and reserve prices) depends only on the current belief about the likelihood of being in the high state. The matching technology and the bargaining protocol are adapted from Satterthwaite and Shneyerov (2008). In fact, our model is essentially a special case of theirs if the state is known, with the main difference being that they allow for heterogeneous values and costs.15 We discuss our set-up with a known state as a benchmark now, before returning to the detailed description of equilibrium. 3.2. Full information benchmark Suppose that $$d\left( h\right) =d\left( \ell \right) =d$$. In this case, the state of the market is known, and we can drop the beliefs from the description of the model. The analysis of the steady state of this case is standard. In particular, let $$V^{S}$$ and $$V^{B}$$ denote the steady-state equilibrium payoffs of the sellers and the buyers, respectively. A standard perfection requirement implies that the sellers’ reserve price satisfies   r−c=δVS. (2) The sellers accept the highest price offer if trading at that price yields higher payoffs than continuing the search and rejects the price offer otherwise. By standard arguments, the buyers’ equilibrium bidding strategies must be fully mixed without atoms and no gaps on some interval $$\left[r, \bar{p}\right]$$, where $$\bar{p}$$ is determined by the buyers’ indifference between the end points,   v−p¯=e−μ(v−r)+δ(1−e−μ)VB, where $$e^{-\mu }$$ is the probability that the seller is matched with no buyer.16 Here, $$v-\bar{p}$$ is the payoff from bidding $$\bar{p}$$ as the highest bid in the support is certain to win. The bid $$r$$ wins only if there is no other bidder, which happens with probability $$e^{-\mu }$$. The lowest bid in the offer distribution must be equal to $$r$$ exactly because it wins only if there is no other bidder. By using a similar indifference condition for intermediate bids, one can characterize the whole distribution of the bids as a function of $$V^{B}$$ and $$V^{S}$$ (determining $$r$$). Then, a fixed-point argument implies the existence of an equilibrium and allows to determine $$V^{S}$$ and $$V^{B}$$ as well. This full-information benchmark is essentially identical to Burdett and Judd (1983), one of the earliest contributions to equilibrium search theory with a non-degenerate distribution of prices. It is a (very) special case of Satterthwaite and Shneyerov (2008), as mentioned before. In our model, the heterogeneity of beliefs takes a somewhat similar role as the heterogeneity of preferences in theirs. In particular, this heterogeneity “purifies” the mixed offer strategy. 3.3. Steady-state equilibrium We now return to our model with $$d\left( h\right) >d\left( \ell \right)$$. A steady-state equilibrium specifies the strategies and the endogenous stocks (the masses of the buyers and sellers and the distribution of their beliefs). We restrict our attention to pure strategy equilibria where the bid is a (weakly) increasing function of the belief of the buyer and the reserve price is (weakly) increasing in the belief of the seller. 3.3.1. Strategies and stocks Formally, the masses of buyers and sellers in the stock are $$D(\omega )$$ and $$S(\omega )$$. The distributions of beliefs are given by c.d.f.s $$\Gamma ^{j}(\cdot |\omega )$$ for $$j=B,S$$ and $$\omega =\ell,h$$. We assume that each function $$\Gamma ^{j}$$ is absolutely continuous, with a density $$\gamma ^{\omega,j}$$ that is right continuous on $$[0,1)$$. The bidding strategy $$\beta$$ is a weakly increasing function and maps beliefs from $$[0,1]$$ to $$[c,v]$$. Moreover, we assume that $$\beta$$ is strictly increasing on the support of $$\Gamma ^{B}$$, so there are no ties. The reserve price strategy $$\rho$$ is a weakly increasing function and maps beliefs from $$[0,1]$$ to $$[c,v]$$. 3.3.2. Trading probabilities Let $$\theta _{(1)}^{B}$$ denote the first-order statistic of the buyers’ beliefs in any given match. We set $$\theta _{(1)}^{B}=0$$, if there is no buyer present. Let $$\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( x|\omega \right)$$ denote the probability that the highest belief in the auction is below $$x$$. The event in which all the buyers have a belief below $$x$$ includes the event in which there are no buyers present at all. The probability of having no buyer present is $$\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( 0|\omega \right)$$ by our assumption that there is no atom in the distribution of beliefs at zero. The Poisson distribution implies $$\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( 0|\omega \right) =e^{-\mu (\omega )}$$, where $$\mu (\omega )=D(\omega )/S(\omega )$$ as defined before. In general, the first-order statistic of the distribution of beliefs is given by   Γ(1)B(x|ω)=e−μ(ω)(1−ΓB(x|ω)). (3) Here, $$\mu (\omega )(1-\Gamma ^{B}\left( x|\omega \right) )$$ is the ratio of the mass of buyers who have a belief above $$x$$ to the mass of sellers, and $$e^{-\mu (\omega )(1-\Gamma ^{B}\left( x|\omega \right) )}$$ is the probability that the seller is matched with no buyer who has such a belief. Given the assumption that the bidding strategies are strictly increasing on the support of $$\Gamma ^{B}$$, a bid $$b$$ wins if (1) there is no bidder in the match with a belief above $$x=\beta ^{-1}\left( b\right)$$ and (2) the seller sets a reserve price of at most $$b$$.17 So, the probability that a buyer wins with bid $$b$$ in state $$\omega$$ is   qB(b|ω):=Γ(1)B(β−1(b)|ω)ΓS(ρ−1(b)|ω). We also refer to $$q^{B}$$ as the per-period trading probability. Similarly, let $$q^{S}(r|\omega )=1-\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \beta ^{-1}\left( r\right) |\omega \right)$$ denote the probability that a seller trades with reserve price $$r$$ in state $$\omega$$. 3.3.3. Updating We first derive the posterior of a buyer upon not trading with bid $$b$$. Bayes’ rule requires that   θ+B(θ,b)=θ(1−qB(b|h))1−(θqB(b|h)+(1−θ)qB(b|ℓ)), (4) if the denominator is strictly positive; otherwise, $$\theta _{+}^{B}$$ is arbitrary. The posterior of a seller who did not trade with reserve price $$r$$ is   θ+S(θ,r)=θ(1−qS(r|h))1−(θqS(r|h)+(1−θ)qS(r|ℓ)); (5) the denominator is always strictly positive. To discuss marginal incentives, it is useful to define the “tieing posterior”. Let $$b_{\left( 1\right) }$$ be the highest bid (with $$b_{\left( 1\right) }=c$$ if there is no bid) and let $$\theta _{0}^{S}\left( \theta,A\right) =\Pr \left( h|b_{\left( 1\right) }\in A,\theta \right)$$ be the posterior probability of $$h$$ conditional on the highest bid being in a (measurable) set $$A$$.18 Taking the conditioning event $$A$$ to be a single bid $$b$$, we obtain $$\theta _{0}^{S}\left( \theta,b\right) =\Pr \left( h|b_{\left( 1\right) }=b,\theta \right)$$. Likewise, $$\theta _{0}^{B}\left( \theta,A\right)$$ is a buyer’s posterior probability of $$h$$ conditional on the highest other bid being in a set $$A$$. Because of the Poisson distribution, $$\theta _{0}^{B}\left( \theta,A\right) =\theta _{0}^{S}\left( \theta,A\right)$$. 3.3.4. Optimality conditions Let $$V^{B}\left( \theta \right)$$ denote the buyers’ value function, which satisfies   VB(θ)=maxbqB(θ,b)(v−b)+δ(1−qB(θ,b))VB(θ+B(θ,b)), (6) with $$q^{B}(\theta,b)=\theta q^{B}(b|h)+(1-\theta )q^{B}(b|\ell )$$. A bidding strategy $$\beta$$ is optimal if $$b=\beta \left( \theta \right)$$ solves problem (6) for every $$\theta$$. Let $$V^{S}\left( \theta \right)$$ denote the sellers’ value function, which satisfies   VS(θ)=maxrqS(θ,r)(E[b(1)|b(1)≥r]−c)+δ(1−qS(θ,r))VS(θ+S(θ,r)), (7) with $$q^{S}(\theta,r)=\theta q^{S}(r|h)+(1-\theta )q^{S}(r|\ell )$$. A reserve-price strategy $$\rho$$ is optimal, if $$r=\rho \left( \theta \right)$$ solves the problem (7) for every $$\theta$$. We impose a notion of perfectness on the sellers’ equilibrium strategies, and require   ρ(1)−c=δVS(1) and ρ(0)−c=δVS(0). (8) Thus, a seller who knows the state accepts prices if and only if accepting the price yields larger payoffs than continued searching. If $$\rho$$ satisfies Equation (8), it is said to be undominated. The condition is similar to the perfection requirement (2) in the full-information benchmark. The main bite of Equation (8) comes in combination with the monotonicity of $$\rho$$, namely, for all $$\theta \in (0,1)$$,   δVS(0)≤ρ(θ)−c≤δVS(1). (9) In particular, Equation (9) rules out “no-trade” equilibria with $$\beta \left( 1\right) =c$$ and $$\rho \left( 0\right) =v$$ because $$V^{S}\left( 1\right) =0$$ requires $$\rho \left( \theta \right) =c$$, for all $$\theta$$. 3.3.5. Steady-state conditions The steady-state stock of sellers needs to satisfy   S(ω)ΓS(θ|ω)=sGS(θ|ω)+δS(ω)∫{τ:θ+S(τ,ρ(τ))≤θ}Γ(1)B(β−1(ρ(τ))|ω)dΓS(τ|ω). (10) To see why, note that the left side is equal to the mass of sellers in the stock at the beginning of a period who have a type below $$\theta$$. The right side is equal to the mass of such sellers at the end of the period, which consists of all those sellers in the inflow with type less than $$\theta$$ (the first term on the right side) plus the mass of sellers who lose, survive, and update to some type less than $$\theta$$ (the second term). In steady state, the mass at the end of a period must be identical to the mass at the beginning.19 The analogous steady-state condition for buyers is   D(ω)ΓB(θ|ω) =dωGB(θ|ω) +δD(ω)∫{τ:θ+B(τ,β(τ))≤θ}(1−Γ(1)B(τ|ω)ΓS(ρ−1(β(τ))|ω))dΓB(τ|ω). (11) 3.3.6. Steady-state equilibrium A steady-state equilibrium in undominated, symmetric, monotone strategies with an atomless distribution of types (abbreviated to steady-state equilibrium or just equilibrium) consists of (i) masses of buyers and sellers, $$S\left( \omega \right), D\left( \omega \right)$$, and distribution functions $$\Gamma ^{B}\left( \cdot |\omega \right)$$, $$\Gamma ^{S}\left( \cdot |\omega \right)$$ for $$\omega \in \left\{ \ell,h\right\}$$, such that the steady-state conditions (10) and (11) hold for all $$\theta$$; (ii) updating functions $$\theta _{+}^{B},\theta _{+}^{S}$$ that are consistent with Bayes’ rule (4), (5); (iii) weakly increasing functions $$\beta$$ and $$\rho$$ that are optimal (solve (6) and (7), respectively), with $$\beta$$ strictly increasing on the support of $$\Gamma ^{B}$$, and (iv) $$\rho$$ is undominated, satisfying (8). Every equilibrium determines (lifetime) trading probabilities $$Q^{j}\left( \theta |\omega \right)$$, expected trading prices $$P^{j}\left( \theta |\omega \right)$$, and expected payoffs $$EU^{j}\left( \theta |\omega \right)$$, for $$j\in \left\{ B,S\right\}$$. With this notation, $$EU^{B}\left( \theta |\omega \right) =Q^{B}\left( \theta |\omega \right) \left( v-P^{B}\left( \theta |\omega \right) \right)$$ and $$EU^{S}\left( \theta |\omega \right) =Q^{S}\left( \theta |\omega \right) \left( P^{S}\left( \theta |\omega \right) -c\right)$$. Similarly, $$V^{j}(\theta )=\theta EU^{j}\left( \theta |h\right) +(1-\theta )EU^{j}\left( \theta |\ell \right)$$. We will be interested in how equilibrium prices and trading probabilities compare with those predicted by market clearing. 3.3.7. Roadmap Section 4 studies a class of equilibria in which sellers accept all equilibrium bids (“full-trade equilibria” ). We show that such equilibria exist, and that, except for the trading price in the low state, the frictionless limit is competitive. Using the explicitly constructed full-trade equilibria, we discuss how learning unfolds. Section 5 then shows that the limit properties of the full-trade equilibria are shared by all steady-state equilibria. Section 6 shows that under a natural refinement, the limit outcome is fully competitive. 4. Full-Trade Equilibria In this section, we prove the existence of “full-trade” equilibria for large $$\delta$$. We start by assuming that sellers are offering a common, exogenously fixed reserve price $$r_{0}$$ and show that there exists a unique “bidding equilibrium” given $$r_{0}$$ for all $$\delta$$. Then, we characterize the limit properties of these bidding equilibria for $$\delta \rightarrow 1$$. Finally, we use these limit properties to argue that for all sufficiently large $$\delta$$, the constraint on the sellers’ behaviour does not bind and the bidding equilibria constitute full equilibria of the original game. All proofs related to the full-trade equilibria are in the Online Appendix. 4.1. Bidding equilibrium: construction and uniqueness Here, we fix an arbitrary $$r_{0}\in \lbrack c,v)$$ and assume that sellers set reserve price $$r_{0}$$. A steady-state bidding equilibrium given $$r_{0}$$ is a combination of stocks and strategies such that (1) the stocks satisfy the steady-state conditions given the strategies, (2) the buyers’ strategy is optimal, and (3) the sellers’ strategy is $$\rho \left( \theta \right) \equiv r_{0}$$; equivalently, we replace the sellers’ optimality condition by $$\rho \left( \theta \right) \equiv r_{0}$$ in the original steady-state equilibrium definition (and drop undominatedness). Proposition 1. For any $$r_{0}\in \lbrack c,v)$$, there exists a unique steady-state bidding equilibrium. The proof is in the Online Appendix. Below is a sketch of the arguments. 4.1.1. Decoupling and the construction of steady-state stocks The buyers bid at least $$r_{0}$$, and thus, all bids are accepted. Moreover, by assumption, $$\beta$$ is strictly increasing on the support of $$\Gamma ^{B}$$. Therefore, given any stock of buyers and sellers, the winning probabilities of any buyer type $$\theta$$ is independent of the exact form of $$\beta$$. This implies also that the posterior belief conditional on losing with an equilibrium bid is independent of $$\beta$$. Together, this allows us to “decouple” the construction of the steady-state stock and $$\beta$$. The construction of the steady-state stock in the Online Appendix uses a recursive algorithm on the cohorts of buyers. This algorithm starts with the exogenously given entering cohort and then recursively determines the cohort that remains in the next period. The difficulty of the construction is to ensure that updating is well behaved during the recursion. Finally, the constructed steady-state stock is shown to be the unique stock that satisfies the steady-state equations. 4.1.2. The bidding strategies Given the unique steady-state stock, we construct the bidding strategies. First, we characterize the bidding equilibrium in a static, reduced-form auction in which we take continuation values as given. Note that the continuation values depend not only on the state but also on the buyers’ beliefs, since the beliefs determine the buyers’ behaviour. Specifically, we suppose that $$W\left( \theta,y\right)$$ is the expected continuation payoff of a buyer if the probability of the high state is $$y$$ and the buyer acts according to belief $$\theta$$. Then, we show that for any $$W$$ that satisfies certain regularity conditions, there exists a unique bidding strategy that forms a mutual best response in the reduced-form auction. This bidding strategy satisfies a standard differential equation with boundary condition $$\beta \left( 0\right) =r_{0}$$. (For more details and a statement of the differential equation determining $$\beta$$, see Section 4.5.) The second step shows that the continuation values are unique. Specifically, we show that in every steady-state bidding equilibrium, continuation value functions $$W$$ have to satisfy certain regularity properties.20 Then, for any given continuation value function that satisfies these properties, the unique bidding strategy found in Step 1 defines a new continuation value if all buyers are bidding according to it. The implied mapping is then shown to be a contraction on the set of “regular” continuation value functions, which establishes both the existence and the uniqueness of the bidding equilibrium. Note that equilibrium existence is shown through an explicit construction: Firstly, the steady-state stocks are constructed using a recursive algorithm on the cohorts. Secondly, a contraction mapping determines the continuation values, and, thirdly, the bidding strategy is a solution to a standard differential equation. Thus, in principle, the bidding equilibria can be numerically constructed and evaluated. 4.2. Limit properties of full-trade bidding equilibria This section characterizes the outcome of full-trade equilibria for $$\delta \rightarrow 1$$. Let $$\left\{ \delta _{k}\right\} _{k=1}^{\infty }$$ be such that the exit rate converges to zero, $$\lim_{k\rightarrow \infty }\left( 1-\delta _{k}\right) =0$$. From Proposition 1, there is a unique bidding equilibrium for each $$\delta _{k}$$. Denote the corresponding equilibrium magnitudes with $$\beta _{k}$$,$$\rho _{k},\Gamma _{k}^{h},\Gamma _{k}^{\ell },D_{k}^{h}$$,$$P_{k}^{j},Q_{k}^{j}$$, and so on. To simplify notation, throughout the article, the term “limit” (and the operator $$\lim$$) refers to a limit over a subsequence such that all the magnitudes of interest are converging.21 We will not repeat this qualification each time, but it is always there. Also, since most limits are with respect to $$k\rightarrow \infty$$, we suppress it and write $$\lim \left( 1-\delta _{k}\right) =0$$ etc. Proposition 2. Suppose $$d^{\ell }c$$, then the limit outcome is almost competitive, except that the price is higher than the competitive price when $$\omega =\ell$$. In the following, we discuss why the proposition holds. Because this discussion is already an almost complete proof and because the proposition is a special case of subsequent results, we do not provide a separate proof.22 (i) The short side trades for sure in each state in the limit in any full-trade equilibrium. Consider $$\omega =h$$. Since $$s1$$ implies $$\lim e^{-\mu _{k}(h)}<1$$.24 Hence, sellers trade with probability converging to 1 as $$\delta _{k}\rightarrow 1$$. Similarly for $$\omega =\ell$$. Here, $$d\left( \ell \right) 0$$, that is, with positive and non-vanishing probability, any buyer is the sole bidder. Therefore, as $$\delta _{k}\rightarrow 1$$, buyers must trade with probability converging to 1. (ii) In the limit, almost all trades take place at prices close to$$r_{0}$$in the low state and close to$$v$$in the high state. Intuitively, bidding in the low state is very non-competitive: Any bid $$r_{0}+\varepsilon$$ guarantees sure winning in the low state in the limit because with positive probability any buyer is the sole bidder, as observed before. Therefore, buyers trade at a price close to $$r_{0}$$ in the low state. Conversely, in the high state, it is not feasible for all buyers to trade with probability 1 since $$s\theta$$. The winner’s curse works differently for the sellers. The pivotal event for a marginal increase in $$r$$ is that the highest bid is equal to the equilibrium reserve price $$r_{0}$$. In the full-trade equilibrium constructed, this pivotal event indicates that the state is likely to be the low state, indicating a low opportunity cost of selling. Therefore, the winner’s curse does not arise for the sellers, and the sellers do not have an incentive to increase their reserve prices. Given that the sellers accept all bids anyway, the scope for the loser’s curse is limited as well. In the equilibrium constructed, the sellers do not decrease their reserve prices over time at all. 5. Limiting Allocations for All Equilibria We argued above that for any sequence of full-trade equilibria, the limiting allocation is competitive with one exception: the limiting transaction price may be above the competitive price in the low state when there is uncertainty about the competitive allocation ($$d^{\ell }0$$ and $$k$$ large enough), so that the optimal bid satisfies $$\lim \beta _{k}\left( 1\right) \leq \lim \rho _{k}\left( 1\right)$$. It follows that $$\lim P_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) =\lim \rho _{k}\left( 1\right)$$. So, $$\lim V_{k}^{S}\left( 1\right) =\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) \left( \rho _{k}\left( 1\right) -c\right)$$. Undominatedness requires that $$\rho _{k}\left( 1\right) -c=\delta _{k}V_{k}^{S}\left( 1\right)$$. Combining these,   limρk(1)−c=limQkS(1|h)(ρk(1)−c). Now, $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) <1$$ implies $$\lim \rho _{k}\left( 1\right) -c=0$$. In words, suppose a seller with type $$\theta =1$$ who is sure of $$\omega =h$$ trades with probability less than 1 but insists on a relatively high reserve price, then, the seller’s continuation payoff is below the payoff from trading at the reserve price, leading the seller to accept lower prices as well by undominatedness—which eventually unravels all the way to $$c$$. Lemma 2. If $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$, then either $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(0|\ell )=1$$ or $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)=v$$ or both. The idea of the proof is as follows. First, $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$ means that sellers are matched with at least one buyer with a positive, non-vanishing probability every period. Now, optimal bidding requires that $$\rho _{k}\left( 0\right) \leq \beta _{k}\left( 0\right)$$, since, otherwise, no seller would accept $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right)$$. But for sellers to accept $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right)$$, it must be unlikely that any buyer bids much higher, meaning, almost all buyers are bidding between $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right)$$ and $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right) +\varepsilon$$, for any $$\varepsilon >0$$ and $$k$$ large enough.31 So, as $$\delta _{k}\rightarrow 1$$, there is an atom in the bid distribution at $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right)$$. Finally, if both, $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(0|\ell )<1$$ and $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)0$$, either $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(0|\ell )=1$$ or $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)=v$$—as claimed. Using Lemmas 1 and 2 to prove Proposition 4. Suppose $$d^{\ell }s$$, it is not feasible that all buyers have payoffs $$v-c$$, since this would require a trading probability of 1. Therefore, $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) <1$$ cannot hold. Now, consider $$\omega =\ell$$. If not all buyers are able to trade with probability converging to 1, then a positive mass of them accumulates, implying that $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$. Also, by the monotonicity of $$\beta _{k}$$, $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(0|\ell )<1$$. So, by Lemma 2, $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)=v$$. But this and $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$ would allow all sellers to trade with probability converging to 1 at a price $$v$$, so that all sellers could ensure a payoff $$v-c$$ in the low state. But this contradicts feasibility since $$d^{\ell }c$$. In the Online Appendix, Proposition 9 shows the following: there exists a sequence of periods $$\left\{ t_{k}\right\} _{k=1}^{\infty }$$ with $$\lim (\delta _{k})^{t_{k}}=1$$, such that all sellers who entered at least $$t_{k}$$ periods ago set a reserve price $$r$$ that is almost surely acceptable to any buyer he is matched with. Since $$\lim (\delta _{k})^{t_{k}}=1$$, the probability of exogenous exit before $$t_{k}$$ vanishes to 0. Thus, similar to the full-trade equilibria, sellers are conceding quickly to buyers in any non-competitive equilibria.32 6. Competitive Limit with Monotone Beliefs 6.1. Off-equilibrium beliefs and information aggregation Proposition 4 shows that steady-state equilibrium outcomes are almost competitive for small frictions, except that prices may be too high in the low state if $$d^{\ell }d^{h}>d^{\ell }$$—sellers are known to be on the long side—prices are close to $$c$$ in every undominated equilibrium. In particular, there is no full-trade equilibrium with sellers setting $$r_{0}>c$$. This is because, given the corresponding bidding equilibrium from Proposition 1, even the highest continuation payoff $$\delta V^{S}\left( 1\right)$$ is bounded strictly below $$r_{0}-c$$ for $$\delta \rightarrow 1$$. Therefore, the reserve price $$r_{0}$$ would be weakly dominated by any reserve price $$r^{\prime }\delta V^{S}\left( 1\right) +c$$: Whatever a seller believes about the state, if the winning bid is in $$\left[ r^{\prime },r_{0}\right]$$, accepting the bid yields strictly higher payoffs than continuation, and otherwise, if the winning bid is not in $$\left[ r^{\prime },r_{0}\right]$$, then it does not matter whether the reserve price is $$r^{\prime }$$ or $$r_{0}$$. Thus, requiring equilibrium to be undominated solves the problem.33 Such an argument no longer works if $$d^{\ell }c$$ for $$\delta \rightarrow 1$$ are supported by off-equilibrium beliefs that put high probability on $$\omega =h$$ if the winning bid is below $$r_{0}$$. However, such off-equilibrium beliefs seem unnatural. First, recall that we already argued that in any full-trade equilibrium, for any $$r_{0}$$ and $$\delta$$ sufficiently large, the probability of $$\omega =h$$ is close to 0 conditional on the winning bid being in $$\left[ r_{0},b^{\prime }\right]$$, for any $$b^{\prime }0$$. Hence, monotonicity requires $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,[r_{0}-\varepsilon,r_{0}])\rightarrow 0$$. In addition, trade occurs with probability converging to $$\frac{d^{\ell }}{s}<1$$ in the low state at a price close to $$r_{0}$$. Together, for any $$\theta \in \left( 0,1\right)$$, continuation payoffs conditional on $$b_{\left( 1\right) }\in \lbrack r_{0}-\varepsilon,r_{0}]$$ satisfy $$\delta V^{S}(\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,[r_{0}-\varepsilon,r_{0}]))\cong \delta V^{S}(0)\cong \frac{d^{\ell }}{s}(r_{0}-c)$$. Thus, the refinement fails for $$b_{1}=r_{0}-\varepsilon$$ and $$b_{2}=r_{0}$$, for $$\varepsilon$$ small enough and $$\delta$$ large enough: Then, the left-hand side of Equation (13) is roughly $$\frac{d^{\ell }}{s}(r_{0}-c)$$, while the right-hand side is roughly $$r_{0}-c$$. The next result shows that this holds more generally. The refinement of monotone beliefs rules out all steady-state equilibria that are not competitive in the limit. Non-competitive equilibria can only be supported by non-monotone beliefs. Proposition 5. The allocation provided by any sequence of steady-state equilibria that satisfy the refinement of monotone beliefs converges to the competitive limit. The proposition is proven in the Appendix. Given Proposition 4, we only need to show that, in the case $$d\left( \ell \right) c$$, any on-path winning bid sufficiently close to $$p_{0}$$ makes the sellers believe that the state is almost surely low. Then, part (i) of the refinement extends this to bids below $$p_{0}$$. Therefore, we can argue that it must be the case that sellers would accept a range of bids below $$p_{0}$$, which upsets any equilibrium in which $$p_{0}>c$$. In the next two sections, we show that equilibrium beliefs are monotone, and we show that there do exist full-trade equilibria that satisfy the refinement. 6.3. Monotone equilibrium updating To motivate the refinement of monotone beliefs, we show that $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,b)=\underset{\varepsilon \rightarrow 0}{\lim }$$$$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,[b,b+\varepsilon ])$$ is increasing in $$b$$ on the support of $$\beta$$ for every steady-state equilibrium for sufficiently large $$\delta$$. This result implies that a higher winning bid in the support of equilibrium bids makes the high state more likely.36 Thus, the refinement restricts the set of equilibria only through its implications for bids that are outside the support of $$\beta$$. Lemma 3. Suppose that $$d^{h}>s>d^{\ell }$$. There exists a $$\underline{\delta }<1$$ such that for all $$\delta >\underline{\delta }$$ the following holds for all steady-state equilibria: For all $$b^{\prime }>b>c$$ such that $$b^{\prime }$$ and $$b$$ are in the support of the equilibrium bid distribution,  θ0S(θ,b′)>θ0S(θ,b). (14) Moreover, let $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,\varnothing )$$ be the posterior if no bid is received. Then, for all $$b>c$$ such that $$b$$ is in the support of the equilibrium bid distribution,  θ0S(θ,b)≥θ0S(θ,∅). (15) The lemma uses the characterization from Proposition 4 given $$d^{\ell }S(h)$$ and $$D(\ell )S(h)$$ and $$D(\ell )\underline{\delta }$$ there exists an equilibrium that satisfies the refinement of monotone beliefs and that has full-trade: For some $$r_{0}$$ and for all $$\theta ^{S}$$ and $$\theta ^{B}$$ in the support of beliefs in the stocks, $$\rho \left( \theta ^{S}\right) \leq r_{0}\leq \beta \left( \theta ^{B}\right)$$. For Proposition 6, we modify our previous construction of a full-trade equilibrium to make sure that for some off-equilibrium beliefs that satisfy the refinement of monotone beliefs, the sellers do not have an incentive to decrease the reserve price below the equilibrium reserve price. To do so, we adopt off-equilibrium beliefs for the sellers that prescribe probability 1 to the lowest bidder type $$\underline{\theta }^{B}$$, if the bid is less than $$\beta _{k}(\underline{\theta }^{B})$$. The key idea is to have type $$\bar{\theta}^{S}$$ (the highest belief in the support) set a reserve price at which he is just indifferent to trade conditional on the winning bid being equal to $$\beta _{k}(\underline{\theta }^{B})$$. Sellers with beliefs below $$\bar{\theta}^{S}$$ strictly prefer accepting $$\beta _{k}(\underline{\theta }^{B})$$, and the refinement can be satisfied by assigning reserve prices strictly below $$\beta _{k}(\underline{\theta }^{B})$$. The resulting equilibria has “full trade” by monotonicity of $$\beta _{k}$$. 7. Discussion 7.1. Alternative matching and bargaining protocols The analysis in Section 6 implies that under full information about market conditions, any steady-state equilibrium has a competitive limit. Therefore, in Proposition 4, the possibility of non-competitive limits arises due to the combination of incomplete information about the economy and the particular matching and bargaining protocol. It is then natural to ask whether, maintaining the assumption of incomplete information about the economy, alternative protocols would yield competitive limits. We start the discussion by observing that, in the present model, the buyers compete directly by bidding, whereas there is no such competition between the sellers. This helps explain why the price is competitive when frictions are low in the case in which there are more buyers than sellers but the price may stay above the competitive level when there are more sellers than buyers. In particular, sellers do not compete away their profits, because they face no direct competition.38 In this section, we argue that when both buyers and sellers face direct competition, the price becomes competitive in both states. Moreover, the amount of direct competition does not have to be large in absolute value, only large compared to the level of frictions. First, consider a modification where, with probability $$\varepsilon >0$$, each buyer is matched with two sellers (and with probability $$1-\varepsilon$$ with one seller). Then the sellers compete, and it is our strong conjecture that the limit must be competitive even in the low state in this case. The reason is that each seller has an incentive to undercut its potential rival to make sure that the buyer chooses his offer. This is sufficient to force the reserve prices down to the cost of the sellers when there are more sellers than buyers in the economy.39 Secondly, consider a setting where buyer competition is limited in that, for any given seller, at most two bids go through for the seller to choose from. We conjecture that this more limited buyer competition is sufficient for the price to be competitive in the high state, as buyers face a Bertrand-type head-on competition with probability 1 in the high state in the limit.40 Therefore, a competitive limit arises as long as there is some but not necessarily overly fierce competition to trade with an agent on the short side. 7.2. Applications and testable implications Online auction markets, especially eBay, are a natural application of our model. In particular, our model predicts that buyers increase their bids over time. Consequently, buyers may later regret not having won at a lower price earlier. Finally, buyers who have already spent more time on the market will win with higher probability. The empirical observations by Juda and Parkes (2006), discussed in the Introduction, are broadly consistent with these predictions. It would be interesting to test systematically for the presence of learning on eBay. More generally, the type of two-sided search model that we study has also been used in the literature to understand decentralized housing and labour markets; see Rogerson et al. (2005). The housing market may fit well, since buyers and sellers are often small households (and, hence, have little experience with the market conditions) and some versions of an auction are indeed used in many countries. Another application of our type of model is over-the-counter asset markets in which individual traders contact each other to bargain over terms or trade; see Duffie et al. (2005) and Duffie (2012).41 Indirect evidence for the presence of aggregate uncertainty is the impact of a reform that increased the post-trade transparency of the over-the-counter U.S. corporate bond market via posting of past transaction terms; see, for example, Bessembinder and Maxwell (2008) and the literature discussed therein. The fact that post-trade transparency affected the market outcome is consistent with the presence of uncertainty about the market condition, at least by some traders; see Duffie et al. (2016) and our discussion of policy implications below. 7.3. Policy implications Despite its stylized nature, our model has some—at least, suggestive—policy implications. Perhaps most significant is that our model shows that decentralized markets can, in principle, achieve the market-clearing outcome, even if no one individually knows what it is. Thus, aggregate uncertainty is not a reason per se to intervene in a market. This may be seen as lending support to Hayek’s conjecture. At least in theory, this was not immediately evident from existing work on decentralized markets—especially given prior negative results in related settings.42 Nevertheless, for large frictions, the outcome is not necessarily (constrained) efficient or market clearing. In this case, “soft” interventions in the form of information provision (transparency) may already be useful. Future extensions of our model could further allow for heterogeneity in values and costs and for costly participation decisions. In these extensions, aggregate uncertainty would imply inefficient trades and inefficient entry choices, allowing the study of interventions that reduce uncertainty. The recent contribution by Duffie et al. (2016) studies such interventions in a model of over-the-counter asset markets. In their work, one market side knows the market conditions. Extensions of our model would allow studying such interventions in settings with more symmetric uncertainty.43 7.4. Discussion of assumptions 7.4.1. Initial signals Newly arriving traders receive an initial signal. This initial signal serves only a technical purpose to avoid the notation related to mixed bidding strategies that would otherwise be necessary. All our results continue to hold if the initial signal is uninformative.44 The fact that it is possible to have no external information in our setting may also clarify the relation to work on the foundation for rational expectations equilibrium with common values, as in Wolinsky (1990) and Golosov et al. (2014). Roughly speaking, in that literature, the question is whether information about the underlying value spreads from the initially “informed” to the “uninformed” traders through trade. 7.4.2. Minimal feedback Information feedback in the trading protocol is minimal, so agents learn only through the failure to trade. Despite the minimal feedback, information aggregation is possible in equilibrium. In principle, it should be possible to extend the characterization results to trading protocols that reveal more information. For example, consider the central arguments behind Proposition 4, namely, Lemmas 1 and 2. These lemmas use very basic arguments that do not rely on details of the protocol such as minimal feedback. Extending the existence results, however, would be more challenging because (1) minimal feedback enabled us to construct the steady-state stock and the strategies separately (“decoupling” ) and (2) more information implies more signalling possibilities, requiring more demanding refinements for which equilibrium existence would be harder to establish. We note that the full-trade equilibria remain equilibria, if sellers observe the winning bid before making an acceptance decision (see the Remark “Seller observing bids before accepting” at the end of Section 4.3). In addition, we establish in a companion paper that sellers have strict incentives to choose a protocol that limits information flows to buyers because the value of continued search is smaller when buyers are uncertain about the state, reducing the value of their outside option; see Lauermann and Virág (2012). 7.4.3. Steady-state and learning with overlapping generations The overall stock of the market is in a steady state, and the underlying market conditions are assumed constant over time. This captures a setting in which traders believe market conditions to be stable relative to the duration of their own search. To us, this belief seems to be relevant in many search environments where there is entry by new traders over time, so that trade and learning continually take place. A model with entry in which different cohorts are continuously mixed to generate a steady distribution of beliefs may, therefore, be a realistic depiction.45 Moreover, despite the stationarity on the aggregate level, the history-dependent, dynamic behaviour of the individuals and cohorts is at the heart of our model and analysis. In particular, potential buyers and sellers learn about market conditions through experimentation over time and change their behaviour as their beliefs change. Finally, although there is no market-wide learning, individual buyers and sellers will almost surely learn the state as frictions become small—and they will do so even if there are no initial signals (meaning that this is true even if all information is endogenously generated by the market). 7.4.4. Simple economy with unit demand/supply The underlying economy is a simple market with unit demand and supply and homogeneous values and costs. There are two reasons for concentrating on such a simple economy. First, the assumption that the good is indivisible captures markets for goods like houses or labour, in which traders engage mostly in one-time transactions. The indivisibility is critical to how learning and experimentation take place. Learning is different if the good is easily divisible because traders can engage in frequent transactions of incremental units; see Golosov et al. (2014). Thus, models with indivisible goods capture different economic scenarios from those with divisible goods. There is also a technical reason for why we concentrate on the case of unit demand and supply. The advantage of our set-up is that types are one-dimensional (beliefs about the state). This makes the analysis transparent, and also allows us to utilize available techniques for analysing auctions and establish the existence of equilibrium. With divisible goods, the effective type becomes two-dimensional—the beliefs and the current endowment of an agent—and so one typically cannot establish equilibrium existence. It may be possible to push the characterization result further. For example, in a previous version (with a slightly different protocol and refinement), we considered a setting with heterogeneous valuations—giving rise to a downward sloping market demand function—and showed market clearing in the limit. However, our methods would not allow us to prove existence with two-dimensional types. 8. Conclusion We study a search market in which the participants do not know the market conditions. We emphasize three contributions to the literature. First, we study the combined effects of search and learning in a novel, two-sided equilibrium search model with uncertainty about market conditions. Secondly, we identify tractable “full-trade equilibria” that provide insights into the economics of decentralized markets and demonstrate how bidding and learning over time takes place. Thirdly, we test the hypothesis that even if decentralized, markets can nevertheless aggregate information that is dispersed among their participants. When frictions are small, trade takes place at the correct market-clearing prices “as if” the participants actually knew demand and supply conditions. We relate the behaviour that leads to this outcome to a “decentralized tâtonnement process”. For small frictions, our analysis suggests that decentralized markets may work well even with uncertainty about the market conditions, despite earlier negative results in related settings. Natural applications of our model include labour markets and housing markets, but models of this kind have also proven useful for over-the-counter asset markets. A number of open questions remain. In particular, to understand the relation with the negative results in Wolinsky (1990) and Blouin and Serrano (2001), for rational expectations equilibrium with common values, it may be useful to study a more general model that nests both of the extreme settings, that is, their pure common value environment and our private value setting. Furthermore, future work may use our algorithm for equilibrium construction to study the market outcome for large frictions: How large is equilibrium price dispersion? How long do traders wait in the market? It would be interesting to quantify the impact of aggregate uncertainty: Can aggregate uncertainty magnify price/wage dispersion and waiting times (unemployment) relative to a market with known demand and supply conditions? APPENDIX Content. This Appendix contains the proofs for the general characterization results from the paper, namely, Propositions 4 and 5 and Lemma 3. All results concerning full-trade equilibria are relegated to a separate Online Appendix. Notation. We abuse notation and write $$Q^{B}\left( \left( \beta,\theta \right) |\omega \right)$$, $$Q^{S}\left( \left( \rho,\theta \right) |\omega \right)$$, $$P^{B}\left( \left( \beta,\theta \right) |\omega \right),$$ etc., for the trading probabilities and the (expected) transaction prices for the allocation of type $$\theta$$ who follows strategy $$\beta$$ or $$\rho$$. Let $$Q^{B}\left( b|\omega \right)$$, $$Q^{S}\left( r|\omega \right)$$, $$P^{B}\left( b|\omega \right),Q^{S}\left( r|\omega \right)$$ denote the trading probability and price variables for the constant bidding strategy $$\beta \equiv b$$ and constant reserve price strategy $$\rho \equiv r$$, respectively. We continue to use the convention that $$\lim$$ refers to a subsequence for which the limit exists, possibly in the extended reals. A. Proof of Proposition 4 We start the proof of Proposition 4 with a number of intermediate results. The first Lemma captures the implications of experimentation becoming cheap as frictions vanish. Lemma 4. Consider any sequence of steady-state equilibria for$$\delta _{k}\rightarrow 1$$. Sellers.If for some$$\theta >0$$it holds that$$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(\theta |h)=1$$, then the realized transaction price of a seller with belief$$\theta$$converges in distribution to a single price$$p^{h}(\theta )\in \lbrack c,v]$$in the high state. If$$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(\theta ^{\prime }|h)=\lim Q_{k}^{S}(\theta ^{\prime \prime }|h)=1$$for some$$1\geq \theta ^{\prime },\theta ^{\prime \prime }>0$$, then$$p^{h}(\theta ^{\prime })=p^{h}(\theta ^{\prime \prime })=p^{h}$$. Moreover, if$$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(\theta |h)=1$$ for some $$\theta <1$$, then $$\lim W_{k}^{S}(\theta |\ell )=\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)$$. Buyers.If for some$$\theta <1$$it holds that$$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\theta |\ell )=1$$, then the realized transaction price of a buyer with belief$$\theta$$converges in distribution to a single price$$p^{\ell}(\theta )\in \lbrack c,v]$$in the low state. If$$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\theta ^{\prime}|\ell )=\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\theta ^{\prime \prime}|\ell )=1$$for some$$0\leq \theta ^{\prime},\theta ^{\prime \prime}<1$$, then$$p^{\ell}(\theta ^{\prime})=p^{\ell}(\theta ^{\prime \prime})=p^{\ell}$$. Moreover, if$$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\theta |\ell )=1$$ for some $$\theta >0$$, then $$\lim W_{k}^{B}(\theta |h)=\lim V_{k}^{B}(1)$$. Proof. We prove the lemma for the sellers’ side only. Fix $$\theta,\theta ^{\prime}>0$$ such that $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(\theta |h)=\lim Q_{k}^{S}(\theta ^{\prime}|h)=1$$ and let $$p^{h}(\theta )=\lim P_{k}^{S}(\theta |h)$$. Step 1. We show that the actual trading price of type $$\theta$$ converges to $$p^{h}(\theta )$$ in probability in the high state. Given $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(\theta |h)=1$$, it follows that there exists a sequence $$t_{k}$$ with $$\lim \delta _{k}^{t_{k}}=1$$ such that the seller trades almost surely by period $$t_{k}$$ in the high state in the limit if he employs his equilibrium strategy. Let $$\chi _{k}(p)$$ denote the probability of selling at price $$p$$ or above by period $$t_{k}$$ if the equilibrium strategy is used by type $$\theta$$. Suppose that for some $$p>p^{h}(\theta )$$, $$\lim \chi _{k}(p)>0$$, otherwise convergence to $$p^{h}(\theta )$$ in probability follows.46 We propose a strategy $$\Sigma (p)$$ with two properties: P1. the seller trades at or above price $$p$$ with a probability converging to $$1$$ in the state $$h$$, P2. the payoff achieved in the low state converges to the (full information) optimal payoff in the state $$\ell$$, $$\lim V_{k}^{S}(0).$$ The strategy $$\Sigma (p)$$ has the following form: the seller sets a reserve price $$p$$ for $$z_{k}$$ periods, where $$z_{k}=\alpha _{k}t_{k}$$. After $$z_{k}$$ periods, if the seller has not traded he adopts a strategy that is optimal in the low state. We require that $$\lim \alpha _{k}=\infty$$, and that $$\lim \delta _{k}^{z_{k}}=1$$.47 This strategy satisfies properties P1 and P2. To see that P1 is satisfied by $$\Sigma (p)$$, we show that the probability of trading by period $$z_{k}$$ (at or above price $$p$$) in the high state converges to 1. Let $$q_{k}$$ denote the probability of trading in the high state by period $$t_{k}$$ if $$\Sigma (p)$$ is used. It holds that $$q_{k}\geq \chi _{k}(p)$$,48 and thus $$\lim \chi _{k}(p)>0$$ implies $$q=\lim q_{k}>0$$. Using, that $$\lim \delta _{k}^{z_{k}}=1,$$ the trading probability offered by strategy $$\Sigma (p)$$ by period $$z_{k}=\alpha _{k}t_{k}$$ in the high state in the limit is   limq+(1−q)q+....(1−q)αk−1q=limq(1−qαk)1−(1−q)=1. To see that P2 is satisfied, note that the exogenous exit probability by period $$z_{k}$$ converges to 0 as $$\lim \delta _{k}^{z_{k}}=1$$. Therefore, the seller drops out with a probability 0 in the limit before he switches to a strategy that is optimal in the low state (at period $$z_{k}$$), and thus his payoff in the low state converges to the full information limiting payoff $$\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)$$.49 It is immediate from P1 and P2 that the original strategy was not optimal, a contradiction with our starting assumption. Step 2: Step 1 implies that a price $$p^{h}(\theta ^{\prime})$$ is achieved almost surely by type $$\theta ^{\prime}$$ in the equilibrium in the high state if $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(\theta ^{\prime}|h)=1$$. If $$p^{h}(\theta ^{\prime})0$$, which concludes the proof. ∥ Proof of Lemma 1. Suppose $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) <1$$. We want to show that $$\lim \rho _{k}(1)=\lim \beta _{k}\left( 1\right) =c$$. From $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) <1$$, it follows that $$\lim 1-q_{k}^{S}\left( \rho _{k}(1)|h\right) =\lim q_{k}^{B}\left( \rho _{k}(1)|h\right) =1$$ (almost no buyer bids above $$\rho _{k}(1)$$). Hence, $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \rho _{k}(1)|h\right) =1$$, so optimality of $$\beta _{k}\left( 1\right)$$ implies $$\lim \beta _{k}\left( 1\right) \leq \lim \rho _{k}(1)$$. From undominatedness (8) and $$V_{k}^{S}\left( 1\right) \leq \beta _{k}(1)-c$$, we have $$\rho _{k}\left( 1\right) -c\leq \delta _{k}\left( \beta _{k}(1)-c\right)$$, and hence $$\rho _{k}\leq \beta _{k}\left( 1\right)$$ for all all $$k$$. Hence, $$\lim \beta _{k}\left( 1\right) =\lim \rho _{k}(1)$$. It follows from the monotonicity of $$\beta _{k}$$ that $$\lim P_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) =\lim \rho _{k}(1)$$. From the definition of $$V_{k}^{S}$$ and Equation (8), for all $$k$$ large enough,   ρk(1)−c=δkVkS(1)=δkQkS(1|h)(PkS(1|h)−c). From the displayed equation, the hypothesis $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) <1$$, and the previous observation $$\lim P_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) =\lim \rho _{k}(1)$$, it follows that $$\lim \rho _{k}(1)=c$$. Since we already showed $$\lim \beta _{k}\left( 1\right) =\lim \rho _{k}(1)$$, the hypothesis $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) <1$$ implies that $$\lim \beta _{k}\left( 1\right) =\lim \rho _{k}(1)=c$$. $$\parallel$$ Proof of Lemma 2. Suppose that $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$. We show that   limQkB(βk(0)|ℓ)<1⇒limβk(0)=v, which proves the lemma. First, $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right) \geq \rho _{k}\left( 0\right)$$. Otherwise, $$V_{k}^{B}\left( 0\right) =0$$, in contradiction to $$\rho _{k}\left( 1\right) -c\leq \delta _{k}\left( v-c\right)$$ implying strictly positive profits when bidding $$b=\rho _{k}\left( 1\right)$$. Hence, by monotonicity of $$\beta _{k}$$ and the hypothesis $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )=\lim \mu _{k}^{\ell}>0$$, we have   limqkS(ρk(0)|ℓ)=lim1−e−μkℓ>0, which implies that   limQkS(θ=0|ℓ)=1. (16) Let $$p^{\ell}:=\lim P_{k}^{S}\left( 0|\ell \right)$$. From (8) and (16), $$\lim \rho _{k}\left( 0\right) =p^{\ell}$$. Of course,   limQkS(ρk(0)+ε|ℓ)<1, (17) for any $$\varepsilon >0$$, by optimality of setting reserve price $$\rho _{k}\left( 0\right)$$ (if $$\rho _{k}\left( 0\right) \rightarrow v$$ such $$\varepsilon$$ does not exist but then the lemma follows directly from $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right) \geq \rho _{k}\left( 0\right)$$). We have   limqkS(bk+ε|ℓ)=lim1−e−μkℓ(1−ΓkB(β−1(bk)|ℓ)=0, where the first equality follows from definition of $$q_{k}^{S}$$ and the second follows from Equation (17). So, $$\lim e^{-\mu _{k}^{\ell}}<1$$ and $$\lim e^{-\mu _{k}^{\ell}(1-\Gamma _{k}^{B}\left( \beta ^{-1}\left( b_{k}\right) |\ell \right)}=1$$. Hence,   limqkB(bk+ε|ℓ)qkB(bk|ℓ):=α = lime−μkℓ(1−ΓkB(β−1(bk)|ℓ)ΓkS(ρk−1(bk+ε)|ℓ)e−μkℓΓkS(ρk−1(bk)|ℓ) ≥ lime−μkℓ(1−ΓkB(β−1(bk)|ℓ)e−μkℓ>1, (18) where the first equality is from the definition of $$q_{k}^{B}$$, the first inequality from $$\Gamma _{k}^{S}\left( \rho _{k}^{-1}\left( b_{k}\right) |\ell \right) \leq \Gamma _{k}^{S}\left( \rho _{k}^{-1}\left( b_{k}+\varepsilon \right) |\ell \right)$$ and the second inequality from the previous findings. Recall   QkB(bk|ℓ)=qkB(bk|ℓ)1−δk1+δkqkB(bk|ℓ)1−δk and so the hypothesis $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\beta _{k}(0)|\ell )<1$$ implies $$\lim \frac{q_{k}^{B}\left( b_{k}|\ell \right)}{1-\delta _{k}}:=z<1$$. Therefore,   QkB(bk+ε|ℓ)QkB(bk|ℓ)=qkB(bk+ε|ℓ)qkB(bk|ℓ)1+δkqkB(bk|ℓ)1−δk1+δkqkB(bk+ε|ℓ)1−δk→α1+z1+zα>1. Thus, if $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)0. (19) Hence, assuming $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)c$$. Then, the monotonicity of $$\rho _{k}$$ and Lemma 1 imply that $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( \theta |h\right) =1$$ for all $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{S},\bar{\theta}^{S} \right]$$, as claimed. Suppose $$\lim \beta _{k}(1)=c$$. We show that this implies a contradiction. As in the proof of Lemma 1, $$\beta _{k}(1)\geq \rho _{k}\left( 1\right)$$, and so $$\lim \rho _{k}\left( 1\right) =c$$. But if $$\lim \rho _{k}\left( 1\right) =\lim \beta _{k}\left( 1\right) =c$$, then the monotonicity of $$\rho _{k}$$ and $$\beta _{k}$$ implies that given any $$\varepsilon$$, a bid $$c+\varepsilon$$ wins for sure when $$k$$ is large enough. Thus, $$\lim V_{k}^{B}\left( \theta \right) =v-c$$ for all $$\theta$$. This requires $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right) =1$$ for almost all $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{B},\bar{\theta}^{B}\right]$$—in contradiction to mass balance given $$d^{h}>s$$: Namely, feasibility requires that   dω∫[0,1]QkB(θ|ω)gB(θ|ω)dθ=s∫[0,1]QkS(θ|ω)gS(θ|ω)dθ. (20) Finally, mass balance requires that $$\lim d^{h}\int_{\underline{\theta} ^{B}}^{\bar{\theta}}Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right) d\theta =s$$. Thus, trading probabilities are competitive if $$\omega =h$$. Take some $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{S},\bar{\theta}^{S}\right]$$ with $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( \theta |h\right) =1$$ and let $$p^{h}:=\lim P_{k}^{S}\left( \theta |h\right)$$. Then, almost all sellers trade at $$p^{h}$$ by $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( \theta |h\right) =1$$ for almost all $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{S},\bar{\theta}^{S}\right]$$ and Lemma 1 (the distribution of trading prices collapses). Thus, the law of one price holds if $$\omega =h$$. Consider $$\omega =\ell$$. Case 1: $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$. Then, from Lemma 2, either $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\beta _{k}(0)|\ell )=1$$ or $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)$$$$=v$$ (or both). If $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\beta _{k}(0)|\ell )=1$$, then by monotonicity of $$\beta _{k}$$, $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\theta |\ell )=1$$ for all $$\theta$$, so the law-of-one-price holds. If $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)$$$$=v$$, then this and $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$ implies that sellers trade for sure when setting $$r=v-\varepsilon$$ for any $$\varepsilon >0$$, $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( v-\varepsilon |\omega \right) =1$$ for all $$\varepsilon$$ and $$\omega =\ell,h$$. Thus, $$\lim V_{k}^{S}\left( \theta \right) =v-c$$ for all $$\theta$$. But this would require $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( \theta \right) =1$$ for all $$\theta$$, violating mass balance (20) given $$d^{\ell}0$$, we obtain that $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )(1-\delta _{k})>0$$. But $$S_{k}(\ell )\left( 1-\delta _{k}\right) \leq s$$—Contradiction. Thus, $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\theta |\ell )=1$$ for almost all $$\theta$$ in case 2. Therefore, trading probabilities are competitive in both possible cases. Take some $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{B},\bar{\theta}\right]$$ with $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right) =1$$ and let $$p^{\ell}:=\lim P_{k}^{\ell}\left( \theta |\ell \right)$$. Then, almost all buyers trade at $$p^{\ell}$$ by Lemma 1. Thus, the law of one price holds if $$\omega =\ell$$. Characterization of payoffs. Consider $$\omega =h$$. From competitive trading probabilities and the law of one price, sellers’ expected payoffs for almost all $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{S},\bar{\theta}\right]$$ are $$\lim EU^{S}\left( \theta |h\right) =\left( p^{h}-c\right)$$. Consider a buyer having type $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{B},\bar{\theta}\right]$$ such that $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right) =1$$. From Lemma 1 and $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right) =1$$ for almost all $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{B},\bar{\theta}\right]$$, we have $$\lim EU^{B}\left( \theta |h\right) =\lim V_{k}^{B}\left( 1\right)$$ for almost all $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{B},\bar{\theta}\right]$$. Moreover, for almost all $$\theta$$, the price conditional on trading is $$p^{\ell}$$. Take some $$\theta$$ with $$\lim EU^{B}\left( \theta |h\right) =\lim V_{k}^{B}\left( 1\right)$$ and $$P_{k}^{B}\left( \theta \right) \rightarrow p^{\ell}$$ and let $$\bar{Q}=\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)$$. Then, $$\lim V_{k}^{B}\left( 1\right) =\bar{Q}\left( v-p^{\ell}\right)$$. Thus, for almost all $$\theta$$, we have $$\bar{Q}=\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)$$. Finally, from the mass balance requirement, $$\lim d^{h}\int_{\underline{\theta}^{B}}^{\bar{\theta}}Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right) d\theta =s$$, and so we have $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right) =\frac{d^{h}}{s}$$ for almost all $$\theta$$, proving $$\lim EU^{B}\left( \theta |h\right) =\frac{d^{h}}{s}\left( v-p^{h}\right)$$. An analogous argument establishes the same for $$\omega =\ell$$. Together, this proves the characterization of payoffs. ∥ Proof of Proposition 4. Proof of Proposition 4 for the case where $$\boldsymbol{d^{\ell}c$$. Then, Lemma 1 implies that $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) =1$$. So, Lemma 1 requires $$P_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) =P_{k}^{S}\left( \theta |h\right)$$ for all $$\theta$$ and from Lemma 5, $$P_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) =p^{h}$$. Thus, by Lemma 1, the probability that some buyer bids higher than $$p^{h}+\varepsilon$$ must vanish for every $$\varepsilon$$. In addition, $$\lim \rho _{k}\left( 1\right) =p^{h}$$ from (8), $$P_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) \rightarrow p^{h}$$ and $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( 1|h\right) =1$$. Hence, a bid $$p^{h}+\varepsilon$$ wins with probability converging to one for every $$\varepsilon >0$$. Thus, $$\lim V_{k}^{B}\left( 1\right) \geq v-p^{h}$$. From Lemma 5 and its proof, $$\lim V_{k}^{B}\left( 1\right) \leq \frac{d^{h}}{s}\left( v-p^{h}\right)$$. Since $$\frac{d^{h}}{s}<1$$, this requires $$p^{h}=v$$. Proof of Proposition 4 for the case where $$\boldsymbol{ss$$, mass balance requires $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$. Thus, from Lemma 2, either $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\beta _{k}(0)|\ell )=1$$ or $$\lim \beta _{k}(0)$$$$=v$$ (or both). Mass balance and $$s0$$ implies that sellers trade for sure when setting $$r=v-\varepsilon$$ for any $$\varepsilon >0$$, that is, $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( v-\varepsilon |\omega \right) =1$$ for all $$\varepsilon$$ and $$\omega =\ell,h$$. Thus, $$\lim V_{k}^{S}\left( \theta \right) =v-c$$ for all $$\theta$$. This implies $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( \theta \right) =1$$ (trading probabilities are competitive), the law of one price with $$p^{h}=p^{\ell}=v$$, and the characterization of payoffs. Proof of Proposition 4 for the case where $$\boldsymbol{s>d^{h}>d^{\ell}}$$. Suppose $$\lim \beta _{k}(1)>c$$. Then, the monotonicity of $$\rho _{k}$$ and Lemma 1 imply that $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}\left( \theta |h\right) =1$$ for all $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{S},\bar{\theta}\right]$$. But this violates mass balance since $$s>d^{h}$$. Thus, $$\lim \beta _{k}(1)=c$$. As argued before in the proof of Lemma 5, when $$\lim \beta _{k}(1)=c$$ then $$\lim V_{k}^{B}\left( \theta \right) =v-c$$ for all $$\theta$$. This requires $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |\omega \right) =1$$ for all $$\theta \in \left[ \underline{\theta}^{B},\bar{\theta}\right]$$ and $$\omega =\ell,h$$. Thus trading probabilities are competitive. Of course, if $$\lim \beta _{k}(1)=c$$, then $$\lim P_{k}^{B}\left( \theta |\omega \right) =\lim P_{k}^{S}\left( \theta |\omega \right) =c$$ (the law of one price holds). The characterization of payoffs follows from $$p^{h}=p^{\ell}=c$$. This completes the proof of Proposition 4. $$\parallel$$ B. Proof of Proposition 5 Remark: The proof of the Proposition uses Lemma 3 (monotone updating on-path) and some of the intermediate steps of its proof, stated in Appendix C. Lemma 6. Take any sequence of equilibria that satisfies the refinement of monotone beliefs, and suppose that $$\lim \theta _{0}^{S}(\theta _{k},b_{k})=0$$ for some sequence $$\left\{ b_{k}\right\}$$ with $$\beta _{k}^{-1}\left( b_{k}\right) \in$$supp $$\Gamma _{k}^{B}$$and $$b_{k}=\rho _{k}(\theta _{k})\rightarrow b\in \lbrack c,v].$$ Then  limVkS(0)+c≥b. Proof. Suppose Lemma 6 does not hold, and take $$b$$ such that $$b>\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c$$, and $$b=\lim b_{k}$$ with $$b_{k}=\rho _{k}(\theta _{k})$$. Take any $$r\in (\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c,b)$$, and we show that the condition for the refinement of monotone beliefs is violated for high enough $$k$$. By point i) of the refinement for every $$\varepsilon >0$$, $$\lim \theta _{0}^{S}(\theta _{k},[b-\varepsilon,b_{k}])=0$$. By point (ii) and the continuity of $$V_{k}^{S}$$, then $$\lim V_{k}^{S}(\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta _{k},[b-\varepsilon,b_{k}]))=\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)>b-\varepsilon -c$$ for all $$\varepsilon >0$$, which implies our claim.∥ Proof of Proposition 5. We need to show that $$p^{\ell}=c$$, where $$p^{\ell}$$ is as defined in Proposition 4 for the case where $$d^{h}>s>d^{\ell}$$. Case 1: $$p^{\ell}=\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c$$. By Proposition 4 and monotonicity of the bid functions and updating, $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(x|\ell )=1$$, for all $$x\geq \underline{\theta}^{B}$$. Therefore, Lemma 1 implies that for $$\omega =\ell$$, almost all buyers trade in the limit at the price $$p^{\ell}$$. Hence, so do the sellers, meaning, $$\lim P_{k}^{S}(z|\ell )=p^{\ell}$$ for almost all $$z\in (0,1)$$. By Proposition 4, $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(z|h)=1$$, and thus Lemma 1 implies $$\lim (W_{k}^{S}(z|\ell )=\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)$$ for all $$z\in (0,1)$$. So, the hypothesis implies $$\lim (W_{k}^{S}(z|\ell )=p^{\ell}-c$$ for almost all $$z$$. Since $$\lim P_{k}^{S}(z|\ell )=p^{\ell}$$, this implies that either $$p^{\ell}=c$$ or $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(z|\ell )=1$$ for almost all $$z\in (0,1)$$—but $$\lim Q_{k}^{S}(z|\ell )=1$$ for almost all $$z\in (0,1)$$ cannot hold by feasibility if $$s>d^{\ell}$$. Hence, $$p^{\ell}=c$$, which implies the claim. Case 2: $$p^{\ell}>\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c.$$ Take any $$z\in \left( \underline{\theta}^{B},\bar{\theta}^{B}\right)$$. From Proposition 4, the monotonicity of $$\beta _{k}$$, and Lemma 3 (monotone updating), $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(z|\ell )=1$$ and $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(z|h)<1$$. Take $$\alpha \in \left( 0,1\right)$$ and let $$t_{k}$$ be the smallest number such that type $$z$$ wins with a probability of at least $$\alpha$$ by period $$t_{k}$$ in state $$\ell$$. With $$\theta _{k}$$ being the posterior after $$t_{k}-1$$ periods, type $$z$$ wins with a probability of at least $$\alpha$$ at a bid of at most $$b_{k}=\beta _{k}\left( \theta _{k}\right)$$ (by monotonicity of $$\theta _{+}$$).51 Such $$t_{k}$$ exists for $$k$$ large enough. From Proposition 4, $$\lim b_{k}=p^{\ell}$$. Also, $$\left( \delta _{k}\right) ^{t_{k}}\rightarrow 1$$. Therefore, the probability that $$z$$ wins with a bid $$b_{k}$$ or lower in state $$h$$ is vanishing to zero. Since $$z$$ wins with a probability not more than $$\alpha$$ before $$t_{k}$$ in state $$\ell$$ and with probability converging to 0 in state $$h$$, we have $$\theta _{k}<1$$. This follows from $$\lim \frac{\theta _{k}}{1-\theta _{k}}=\lim \frac{z}{1-z}\frac{\Pr \left( \text{no win before}t_{k}-1|h\right)}{\Pr \left( \text{no win before}t_{k}-1|\ell \right)}<\frac{\bar{\theta}^{B}}{1-\bar{\theta}^{B}}\frac{1}{1-\alpha}$$. Step 1. For all $$x_{k}\leq \bar{\theta}^{S}$$ and $$b_{k}=\beta _{k}\left( \theta _{k}\right)$$ (as defined above),   limθ0S(xk,bk)=0. (21) From $$\gamma _{k\left( 1\right)}=\gamma _{k}^{B}(\theta _{k}|\omega )\frac{D_{k}(\omega )}{S_{k}(\omega )}e^{-\frac{D_{k}(\omega )}{S_{k}(\omega )} (1-\Gamma _{k}^{B}(\theta _{k}|\omega ))}$$, we have   θ0S(xk,bk)1−θ0S(xk,bk)=xk1−xkDk(h)Sk(h)Dk(ℓ)Sk(ℓ)γkB(θk|h)γkB(θk|ℓ)e−Dk(h)Sk(h)(1−ΓkB(θk|h))e−Dk(ℓ)Sk(ℓ)(1−ΓkB(θk|ℓ)). Note that the distribution of beliefs must satisfy   Dk(h)Dk(ℓ)γkB(θk|h)γkB(θk|ℓ)=θk1−θk. (22) This follows from the Bayesian consistency of the distribution of posterior beliefs.52 Also, by construction $$S_{k}(\ell )\leq \frac{s}{1-\delta _{k}}$$ and $$S_{k}(h)\geq s$$ hold. Therefore, upon substitution, we obtain   θ0S(xk,bk)1−θ0S(xk,bk)≤xk1−xkθk1−θk11−δke−Dk(h)Sk(h)(1−ΓkB(θk|h))e−Dk(ℓ)Sk(ℓ)(1−ΓkB(θk|ℓ)). By assumption, $$x_{k}\leq \bar{\theta}^{S}<1$$, and we already argued $$\lim \theta _{k}<1$$. Also, $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )=0$$ by Lemma 2, and thus $$\lim e^{-\frac{D_{k}(\ell )}{S_{k}(\ell )}(1-\Gamma _{k}^{B}(\theta _{k}|\ell ))}=1$$. Therefore, it is sufficient to prove that   lime−Dk(h)Sk(h)(1−ΓkB(θk|h))1−δk=0. From $$\left( \delta _{k}\right) ^{t_{k}}\rightarrow 1$$ and $$\lim Q_{k}^{B}(\theta |h)<1$$ for all $$\theta \leq \bar{\theta}$$, we have $$\lim (1-\Gamma _{k}^{B}(\theta _{k}|h))=0$$. Finally, by Lemma 5 it holds that $$\lim \frac{D_{k}(h)(1-\delta _{k})}{S_{k}(h)}=z>0$$. Therefore, $$\lim \frac{e^{-\frac{D_{k}(h)}{S_{k}(h)}(1-\Gamma _{k}^{B}(\theta _{k}|h))}}{1-\delta _{k}}=\lim \frac{e^{-\frac{z}{1-\delta _{k}}}}{1-\delta _{k}}=0$$, and so Equation (21) holds. Step 2. For any $$\varepsilon$$ and $$k$$ large enough, $$\rho _{k}\left( \theta \right) \notin \lbrack V_{k}^{S}(0)+c+\varepsilon,b_{k}]$$ for all $$\theta \leq \bar{\theta}^{S}$$ (and recall $$b_{k}\rightarrow p^{\ell}>\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c$$). First, we show that for all $$b\in \lbrack \lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c+\varepsilon,p^{\ell}]$$, $$\beta _{k}^{-1}\left( b\right) \in$$supp $$\Gamma _{k}^{B}$$for a large enough $$k$$. Otherwise, there exists an interval $$(\underline{b}, \overline{b})\subset \lbrack \lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c+\varepsilon,p^{\ell}]$$ that is not in the limit of the supports of the bid distributions but $$\overline{b}$$ is. Then for it to be optimal to bid close to $$\overline{b}$$ in the limit, it must hold that $$\overline{b}$$ is in the limit of the supports of the reserve price distributions. But then Lemma 6 implies that $$\overline{b}\leq \lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c$$, a contradiction. Secondly, suppose that for some $$r\in \lbrack \lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c+\varepsilon,b_{k}]$$ it holds that $$r$$ is in the limiting support of the reserve price distribution. Then again Lemma 6 yields a contradiction. Step 3. Given any $$\varepsilon$$ small enough and $$k$$ large enough, bidding $$b_{k}^{\prime}=V_{k}^{S}(0)+c+\varepsilon$$ is strictly more profitable for $$\theta _{k}$$ than bidding $$b_{k}$$. By the hypothesis of the case, $$\lim b_{k}^{\prime}<\lim b_{k}=p^{\ell}$$. In addition, the probability that there is no other buyer converges to one when $$\omega =\ell$$. Hence, given Step 2, conditional on $$\omega =\ell$$, bidding $$b_{k}^{\prime}$$ strictly increases payoffs for $$\theta _{k}$$ since $$b_{k}^{\prime}$$ wins with the same probability as $$b_{k}$$ in the low state in the limit: $$\lim \frac{q_{k}^{B}(b_{k}^{\prime}|\ell )}{q_{k}^{B}(b_{k}|\ell )}=1$$. Next, observe that by Step 1 and the refinement of monotone beliefs $$\lim \theta _{0}^{S}(\theta _{k},[b_{k}^{\prime},b_{k}])=0$$. Therefore, conditional on winning against bids on $$[b_{k}^{\prime},b_{k}]$$, the state is almost sure to be low in the limit. But in the low state, it is more profitable to place bid $$b_{k}^{\prime}$$ as we argued above, and Step 3 is complete. Thus, we have reached a contradiction and so Case 2 cannot occur. Since the claim holds in Case 1, this completes the proof of Proposition 5. $$\parallel$$ C. Monotone updating and Proof of Lemma 3 We prove monotonicity of certain posteriors for the case where $$d^{h}>s>d^{\ell}$$. We start the analysis with the following result: Lemma 7. If $$\delta$$ is large enough, then $$\frac{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ and $$\frac{\gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ are strictly increasing in $$\theta$$ for all $$\theta \geq \underline{\theta}^{B}$$ on the support of $$\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}$$. Proof. Recall that $$\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\omega \right) =e^{-\frac{D(\omega )}{S(\omega )}(1-\Gamma ^{B}\left( \theta |\omega \right) )}$$, and thus   γ(1)B(θ|ω)=D(ω)S(ω)γB(θ|ω)Γ(1)B(θ|ω). The likelihood ratio can be written as   γ(1)B(θ|h)γ(1)B(θ|ℓ)=D(h)S(h)γB(θ|h)Γ(1)B(θ|h)D(ℓ)S(ℓ)γB(θ|ℓ)Γ(1)B(θ|ℓ). From Equation (22),   D(h)D(ℓ)γB(θ|h)γB(θ|ℓ)=θ(1−θ), (23) and thus   γ(1)B(θ|h)γ(1)B(θ|ℓ)=S(ℓ)S(h)θ1−θΓ(1)B(θ|h)Γ(1)B(θ|ℓ). (24) Suppose that for all $$\theta \in supp\Gamma _{{}}^{B}$$ it holds that $$\frac{S(\ell )}{S(h)}\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}>1$$. Then $$\frac{\gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}>\frac{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$, so $$\frac{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is increasing in $$\theta$$ because   (Γ(1)B(θ|h)Γ(1)B(θ|ℓ))′=γ(1)B(θ|h)Γ(1)B(θ|ℓ)−γ(1)B(θ|ℓ)Γ(1)B(θ|h)(Γ(1)B(θ|ℓ))2  =γ(1)B(θ|ℓ)Γ(1)B(θ|ℓ)(γ(1)B(θ|h)γ(1)B(θ|ℓ)−Γ(1)B(θ|h)Γ(1)B(θ|ℓ)). Moreover, $$\frac{\gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}=\frac{\frac{D(h)}{S(h)}\theta \Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\frac{D(\ell )}{S(\ell )}(1-\theta )\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is also increasing in $$\theta$$. Therefore, we only to need to establish that $$\theta \in supp\Gamma _{{}}^{B}$$ implies $$\frac{S(\ell )}{S(h)}\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}>1$$ for $$\delta$$ large enough. Let the per period trades have mass $$t(\omega )$$ for $$\omega =\ell,h$$. Then $$S(\omega )=\frac{s-t(\omega )}{1-\delta}$$ in a steady state.53 By feasibility $$t(\ell )\leq d^{\ell}$$, and by the fact that the limit is competitive in the high state we have that $$\lim S_{k}(h)(1-\delta _{k})=s-\lim t_{k}(h)=0$$. Therefore, we obtain that $$\lim S_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(h)=\infty$$ and thus $$\frac{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is increasing for all $$\theta \geq \underline{\theta}^{B}$$. ∥ Next, we establish Lemma 3. Recall that $$\theta _{+}^{B}(\theta,b)$$ is the posterior of a buyer who starts with belief $$\theta$$, and learns that the bid $$b$$ did not win (either there was a higher bidder or the seller had set a higher reserve price). Lemma 8. Assume $$d^{h}>s>d^{\ell}$$. There exists a $$\underline{\delta}<1$$ such that for all $$\delta >\underline{\delta}$$ the following holds. Buyers update upward, that is  θ+B(θ,b)>θfor all$$b\in \lbrack \beta (\underline{\theta}^{B}),\beta (1))$$. Proof. Let $$F_{b}^{\omega}(x)=\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}(\beta ^{-1}(x)|\omega )$$ denote the probability that the highest bid is less than or equal to $$x$$ in state $$\omega$$. Similarly, let $$F_{r}^{\omega}(x)=\Gamma ^{S}(\rho ^{-1}(x)|\omega )$$ denote the probability that the reserve price set is less than or equal to $$x$$ in state $$\omega$$. Given previous results, it holds that $$F_{b}^{\omega}(x)=e^{-\frac{D(\omega )}{S(\omega )}(1-\Gamma _{{}}^{B}\left( \beta ^{-1}(x)|\omega \right) )}$$. In the main text we show that $$F_{b}^{\omega}(x)=\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \beta ^{-1}(x)|\omega \right)$$ and $$F_{r}^{\omega}(x)=\Gamma ^{S}\left( \rho ^{-1}(x)|\omega \right)$$. By definition,   θ+B(θ,b)1−θ+B(θ,b)=θ1−θ1−Fbh(b)Frh(b)1−Fbℓ(b)Frℓ(b). Note, that $$F_{b}^{\omega}(r)=\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \beta ^{-1}(r)|\omega \right)$$ and thus the fact that $$\frac{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is strictly increasing in $$\theta$$ for all $$\theta \geq \underline{\theta}^{B}$$ by Lemma 7 implies that $$\frac{F_{b}^{h}(r)}{F_{b}^{\ell}(r)}$$ is increasing in $$r$$ for all $$r\geq \beta (\underline{\theta}^{B})$$. By construction, $$\frac{F_{b}^{h}(\beta (1))}{F_{b}^{\ell}(\beta (1))}=1$$ holds. These two observations imply that for all $$b\in \lbrack \beta (\underline{\theta}^{B}),\beta (1))$$, it holds that $$\frac{F_{b}^{h}(b)}{F_{b}^{\ell}(b)}<1$$. Therefore, it is sufficient to show that $$\frac{F_{r}^{h}(b)}{F_{r}^{\ell}(b)}\leq 1$$. We show that $$\frac{F_{r}^{h}(b)}{F_{r}^{\ell}(b)}$$ is weakly increasing in $$b$$ and we know that by construction $$\frac{F_{r}^{h}(\beta (1))}{F_{r}^{\ell}(\beta (1))}=1$$, which concludes our proof. The requirement that $$\frac{F_{r}^{h}(b)}{F_{r}^{\ell}(b)}$$ is weakly increasing in $$b$$ for all $$b\geq \beta (\underline{\theta}^{B})$$ is equivalent to $$\frac{\Gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\Gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is increasing in $$\theta$$ for all $$\theta \geq \underline{\theta}^{S}$$. The analogue of Equation (22) for the sellers implies that $$\frac{\gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}=\frac{S(\ell )}{S(h)}\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}$$. Therefore, $$\frac{\gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is strictly increasing in $$\theta$$, which implies that $$\frac{\Gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\Gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is increasing in $$\theta$$ as well.54 ∥ Another consequence of Lemma 7 is that updating is monotone for the sellers as well. Formally, let $$\theta _{+}^{S}(\theta,r)$$ be the posterior of a seller who starts with belief $$\theta$$, and learns that the highest bid is less than $$r$$ (including the event that there is no bidder present at all). Lemma 9. Assume $$d^{h}>s>d^{\ell}$$. There exists $$\underline{\delta}<1$$ such that for all $$\delta >\underline{\delta}$$ the following holds. In every equilibrium, sellers update downward, that is  θ+S(θ,r)<θ for all$$r\in \lbrack c,v]$$ and $$\theta \in (0,1)$$. Moreover, a lower reserve price yields stronger updating, that is,$$\theta _{+}^{S}(\theta,r)$$is weakly increasing in$$r$$for all$$r\geq \beta (\underline{\theta}^{B})$$, and if$$\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}(r^{\prime}|\omega )>\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}(r|\omega )$$, then $$\theta _{+}^{S}(\theta,r^{\prime})>\theta _{+}^{S}(\theta,r)$$. Proof. Recall that $$F_{b}^{\omega}(x)=\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}(\beta ^{-1}(x)|\omega )$$. Lemma 3 implies that since buyers update upwards for any $$\theta \geq \underline{\theta}^{B}$$, and strategies are monotone thus the buyers never place any bid lower than $$\beta (\underline{\theta}^{B})$$ in equilibrium. Therefore, for all $$r<\beta (\underline{\theta}^{B})$$ it holds that $$\theta _{+}^{S}(\theta,r)=\theta _{+}^{S}(\theta,\beta (\underline{\theta}^{B}))$$ and thus it is sufficient to prove $$\theta _{+}^{S}(\theta,r)<\theta$$ for all $$r\geq \beta (\underline{\theta}^{B})$$. By definition,   θ+S(θ,r)1−θ+S(θ,r)=θ1−θFbh(r)Fbℓ(r). (25) In the proof of Lemma 3, we showed that $$\frac{F_{b}^{h}(r)}{ F_{b}^{\ell}(r)}<1$$ for all $$r\in \lbrack \beta (\underline{\theta} ^{B}),\beta (1))$$, which then implies the first claim via Equation (25). The second result is a direct consequence of the fact that $$\frac{F_{b}^{h}(r)}{F_{b}^{\ell}(r)}$$ is increasing in $$r$$ by 7. ∥ Finally, we prove Lemma 3. Proof of Lemma 3. Take any $$b^{\prime}>b\geq c$$ such that $$\beta ^{-1}\left( b^{\prime}\right)$$ and $$\beta ^{-1}\left( b\right)$$ are in the support of $$\Gamma ^{B}$$. We want to show that $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,b)>\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,b^{\prime})$$. Let $$\theta ^{B}$$ and $$\widetilde{\theta}^{B}$$ be such that $$b=\beta (\theta ^{B})$$ and $$b^{\prime}=\beta (\widetilde{\theta}^{B})$$. Notice that $$\widetilde{\theta}^{B}>\theta ^{B}\geq \underline{\theta}^{B}$$ by the bids being in the support of equilibrium bids as discussed after the proof of the previous Lemma. Bayes rule implies that   θ0S(θ,b)1−θ0S(θ,b)=θ1−θγ(1)B(θB|h)γ(1)B(θB|ℓ)<θ1−θγ(1)B(θ~B|h)γ(1)B(θ~B|ℓ), which establishes the first result upon using Lemma 7. The posterior if no bid is received is $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,\varnothing )$$. We want to show that for all $$b\geq 0$$ such that $$\beta ^{-1}\left( b\right) \in supp(\Gamma ^{B})$$, $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,b)\geq \theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,\varnothing )$$. To establish this, it is sufficient to prove $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,\beta (\underline{\theta}^{B}))\geq \theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,\varnothing ),$$ which boils down to   γ(1)B(θ_B|h)γ(1)B(θ_B|ℓ)≥Γ(1)B(θ_B|h)Γ(1)B(θ_B|ℓ) (26) upon noting that $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,\varnothing )=\frac{\theta}{1-\theta}\frac{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \underline{\theta}^{B}|h\right)}{\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \underline{\theta}^{B}|\ell \right)}$$ because the probability of not receiving any bid in state $$\omega$$ is $$\Gamma _{(1)}^{B}\left( \underline{\theta}^{B}|\omega \right)$$. Using Equations (24), (26) can be rewritten as   S(ℓ)S(h)θ_B1−θ_B≥1, which holds for a large enough $$\delta$$ as we argued in the proof of Lemma 7. $$\parallel$$ Acknowledgments We have benefited from comments by Georg Nödeke, Tilman Börgers, Jan Eeckhout, Leonardo Felli, Chris House, Daniel Krähmer, Philipp Kircher, Benny Moldovanu, Tymofiy Mylovanov, Marco Ottaviani, Art Shneyerov, and the anonymous referees, as well as seminar audiences at Boston College, Cambridge, Columbia, Concordia University, Essex, Madison–Wisconsin, Michigan, Michigan State, NYU Stern, OSU, Queen Mary University, Penn State University, the University of Toronto, the Canadian Economic Theory Conference, the MaCII 2016 Workshop, the Decentralization Conference at Washington University, the 2nd MEDS Theory workshop in Graz, the Southampton Winter Workshop, and the Midwest Theory Conference. We thank Deniz Kattwinkel, Isaac Sorkin, and Qinggong Wu for research assistance. Stephan Lauermann acknowledges the National Science Foundation for financial support under Grant SES-1061831. Supplementary Data Supplementary data are available at Review of Economic Studies online. References AUSUBEL L. M., CRAMTON P. and DENECKERE R. J. ( 2002), “Bargaining with Incomplete Information”, Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications , 3, 1897– 1945. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   BANERJEE A. and FUDENBERG D. ( 2004), “Word-of-Mouth Learning”, Games and Economic Behaviour , 46, 1– 22. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   BENABOU R. and GERTNER R. ( 1993), “Search with Learning from Prices: Does Increased Inflationary Uncertainty Lead to Higher Markups?”, The Review of Economic Studies , 60, 69– 93. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   BESSEMBINDER H. and MAXWELL W. ( 2008), “Markets: Transparency and the Corporate Bond Market”, Journal of Economic Perspectives , 22, 217– 234. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   BLOUIN M. R. and SERRANO R. ( 2001), “A Decentralized Market with Common Values Uncertainty: Non-Steady States”, Review of Economic Studies , 68, 323– 46. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   BURDETT K. and JUDD K. L. ( 1983), “Equilibrium Price Dispersion”, Econometrica , 51, 955– 969. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   CRIPPS M. W. and SWINKELS J. M. ( 2006), “Efficiency of Large Double Auctions”, Econometrica , 74, 47– 92. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   DANA J. D. ( 1994), “Learning in an Equilibrium Search Model”, International Economic Review , 35, 745– 771. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   DIAMOND P. A. ( 1971), “A Model of Price Adjustment”, Journal of Economic Theory , 3, 156– 168. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   DUFFIE D., DWORCZAK P. and ZHU H. ( 2016), “Benchmarks in Search Markets”, Journal of Finance  (Forthcoming). DUFFIE D., GARLEANU N. and PEDERSEN L. H. ( 2005), “Over-the-Counter Markets”, Econometrica , 73, 1815– 1847. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   DUFFIE D. and MANSO G. ( 2007), “Information Percolation in Large Markets”, American Economic Review , 97, 203– 209. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   DUFFIE D. and SUN Y. ( 2007), “Existence of Independent Random Matching”, The Annals of Applied Probability , 17, 386– 419. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   DUFFIE D. ( 2012), Dark Markets: Asset Pricing and Information Transmission in Over-the-Counter Markets  ( New Jersey: Princeton University Press). FELLI L. and ROBERTS K. ( 2016), “Does Competition Solve the Hold-up Problem?”, Economica , 83, 172– 200. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   FUDENBERG D. and LEVINE D. K. ( 1993), “Steady State Learning and Nash Equilibrium”, Econometrica , 61, 547– 573. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   GALE D. ( 1987), “Limit Theorems for Markets with Sequential Bargaining”, Journal of Economic Theory , 43, 20– 54. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   GOLOSOV M., LORENZONI G. and TSYVINSKI A. ( 2014), “Decentralized Trading with Private Information”, Econometrica , 82, 1055– 1091. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   GOLUB B. and JACKSON M. O. ( 2010), “Naive Learning in Social Networks and the Wisdom of Crowds”, American Economic Journal: Microeconomics , 2, 112– 49. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   GOTTARDI P. and SERRANO R. ( 2005), “Market Power and Information Revelation in Dynamic Trading”, Journal of the European Economic Association , 3, 1279– 1317. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   HAYEK F. A. ( 1945), “The Use of Knowledge in Society”, The American Economic Review , 35, 519– 530. JANSSEN M., PARAKHONYAK A. and PARAKHONYAK A. ( 2014), “Non-reservation Price Equilibria and Consumer Search” (Mimeo). JANSSEN M. and SHELEGIA S. ( 2015), “Consumer Search and Double Marginalization”, American Economic Review , 105, 1683– 1710. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   JEHIEL P. and LAMY L. ( 2015), “On Absolute Auctions and Secret Reserve Prices”, The RAND Journal of Economics , 46, 241– 270. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   JUDA A. I. and PARKES D. C. ( 2006), “The Sequential Auction Problem on Ebay: An Empirical Analysis and a Solution”, In Proceedings of the 7th ACM Conference on Electronic Commerce, Ann Arbor, MI , 180– 189. KUNIMOTO T. and SERRANO R. ( 2004), “Bargaining and Competition Revisited”, Journal of Economic Theory , 115, 78– 88. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   KYLE A. S. ( 1989), “Informed Speculation with Imperfect Competition”, Review of Economic Studies , 56, 317– 55. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   LAUERMANN S. and VIRÁG G. ( 2012), “Auctions in Markets: Common Outside Options and the Continuation Value Effect”, American Economic Journal: Microeconomics , 4, 107– 130. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   LAUERMANN S. and WOLINSKY A. ( 2016), “Search with Adverse Selection”, Econometrica , 84, 243– 315. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   LAUERMANN S. ( 2012), “Asymmetric Information in Bilateral Trade and in Markets: An Inversion Result”, Journal of Economic Theory , 147, 1969– 1997. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   LAUERMANN S. ( 2013), “Dynamic Matching and Bargaining Games: A General Approach. The American Economic Review , 103, 663– 689. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   MAJUMDAR D., SHNEYEROV A. and XIE H. ( 2015), “An Optimistic Search Equilibrium”, Review of Economic Design , 20, 89– 114. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   MILCHTAICH I. ( 2004), “Random-player Games. Games and Economic Behaviour , 47, 353– 388. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   MORTENSEN D. T. ( 1982), “The Matching Process as a Noncooperative Bargaining Game”, in McCall J.J. ed., The Economics of Information and Uncertainty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. MYERSON R. B. ( 1998), Extended poisson games and the condorcet jury theorem. Games and Economic Behaviour , 25, 111– 131. CrossRef Search ADS   OSTROVSKY M. ( 2012), “Information Aggregation in Dynamic Markets with Strategic Traders”, Econometrica , 80, 2595– 2647. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   PESENDORFER W. and SWINKELS J. ( 1997), “The Loser’s Curse and Information Aggregation in Common Value Auctions”, Econometrica , 65, 1247– 1282. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   PESENDORFER W. and SWINKELS J. ( 2000), “Efficiency and Information Aggregation in Auctions”, American Economic Review , 90, 499– 525. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   RENY P. J. and PERRY M. ( 2006), “Toward a Strategic Foundation for Rational Expectations Equilibrium”, Econometrica , 74, 1231– 1269. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   ROGERSON R., SHIMER R. and WRIGHT R. ( 2005), “Search-Theoretic Models of the Labour Market: A Survey”, Journal of economic literature , 43, 959– 988. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   ROSTEK M. and WERETKA M. ( 2012), “Price Inference in Small Markets”, Econometrica , 80, 687– 711. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   RUBINSTEIN A. and WOLINSKY A. ( 1985), “Equilibrium in a Market with Sequential Bargaining”, Econometrica , 53, 1133– 50. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   SATTERTHWAITE M. and SHNEYEROV A. ( 2007), “Dynamic Matching, Two-sided Incomplete Information, and Participation Costs: Existence and Convergence to Perfect Competition”, Econometrica , 75, 155– 200. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   SATTERTHWAITE M. and SHNEYEROV A. ( 2008), “Convergence to Perfect Competition of a Dynamic Matching and Bargaining Market with Two-sided Incomplete Information and Exogenous Exit Rate”, Games and Economic Behaviour , 63, 435– 467. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   SERRANO R. and YOSHA O. ( 1993), “Information Revelation in a Market with Pairwise Meetings: The One Sided Information Case”, Economic Theory , 3, 481– 99. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   SHNEYEROV A. and WONG C. L. ( 2010), The Rate of Convergence to Perfect Competition of Matching and Bargaining Mechanisms” Journal of Economic Theory , 145, 1164– 1187. CrossRef Search ADS   SMITH L. and SORENSEN P. N. ( 2013), “Rational Social Learning by Random Sampling”, Available at SSRN 1138095 . SMITH L. ( 2011), “Frictional Matching Models”, Annual Review of Economics , 3, 319– 38. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS   VIVES X. ( 2010), Information and Learning in Markets: The Impact of Market Microstructure  ( New Jersey: Princeton University Press). WOLINSKY A. ( 1990), “Information Revelation in a Market with Pairwise Meetings”, Econometrica , 58, 1– 23. Google Scholar CrossRef Search ADS PubMed  Footnotes 1. In fact, based on insights from conventional search theory, Juda and Parkes (2006) conclude that these observations suggest that buyers make mistakes. 2. The auction protocol captures that there is often some degree of direct competition and this protocol helps by simplifying the analysis; see Section 4.4. 3. Conditional on winning, the buyers also learn from the fact that the seller’s reservation price was lower than the accepted bid. This learning pattern reinforces the winner’s curse, as sellers set low reserve prices when the state is likely to be low. 4. Thus, the loser’s curse refers to the effect of the learning dynamics over time, whereas the winner’s curse refers to bid shading in each period. 5. For recent contributions, see, for example, Satterthwaite and Shneyerov (2007, 2008), Shneyerov and Wong (2010), Kunimoto and Serrano (2004), Lauermann (2012, 2013), and the references therein. Most of these contributions study settings with private information. 6. An exception is Janssen et al. (2014). 7. Majumdar et al. (2015) is the only other paper that considers a dynamic matching and bargaining game with aggregate uncertainty. However, they assume that traders are subjectively certain about the market conditions. 8. Serrano and Yosha (1993) consider a related problem with one-sided private information, and Gottardi and Serrano (2005) consider a “hybrid” model of decentralized and centralized trading. Lauermann and Wolinsky (2016) study information aggregation if a single, privately informed buyer searches among many sellers. 9. To make their model tractable, Wolinsky (1990) and Blouin and Serrano (2001) assume that traders choose between only two price offers (bargaining postures). It is an open question whether the trading outcomes in these models are competitive with small frictions if prices can be chosen freely. 10. Examples are the work on large double auctions by Reny and Perry (2006), Cripps and Swinkels (2006), and Pesendorfer and Swinkels (1997, 2000), as well as the work on information aggregation in Cournot models, summarized in Vives (2010), and in financial markets (e.g. Kyle, 1989; Ostrovsky, 2012; Rostek and Weretka, 2012). 11. One can easily verify that the density of posteriors must satisfy $$\theta =\frac{\left( 0.5\right) d^{h}g^{B}(\theta |h)}{\left( 0.5\right) d^{h}g^{B}(\theta |h)+\left( 0.5\right) d^{\ell }g^{B}(\theta |\ell )}$$, and, hence, $$\frac{\theta }{1-\theta }=\frac{d^{h}}{d^{\ell }}\frac{g^{B}(\theta |h)}{g^{B}(\theta |\ell )}$$. This formula expresses the Bayesian consistency of the distribution of posterior beliefs. Smith and Sorensen (2013) call it the no-introspection property: “If the individual further updates his private belief $$\theta$$ by asking of its likelihood in the two states of the world, he must learn nothing more.” An implication is that $$G^{B}\left( \cdot |h\right)$$ dominates $$G^{B}\left( \cdot |\ell \right)$$ in the likelihood ratio ordering. We will later use an analogous property for the distribution of beliefs in the entire population, and not just for beliefs of the entering cohort. 12. To formally define updating based on entering the market, suppose that there is a potential set of buyers of mass $$d$$, with $$d\geq d(h)$$. In state $$\omega$$, a mass $$d(\omega )$$ of the potential buyers actually enters the market. Alternatively, one can simply interpret $$d(h)/d(\ell)$$ as the prior of an entering buyer. For games with population uncertainty and updating about an unknown state of nature, see Myerson (1998) and, especially, Milchtaich (2004). 13. Because the belief conditional on entering (but without conditioning on the signal) is equal to $$d^{h}/(d^{h}+d^{\ell })>1/2$$, the assumption holds if $$\frac{g_{s}^{B}(x|h)}{g_{s}^{B}(x|\ell )}$$ is sufficiently close to one for all $$x\in \left[ 0,1\right]$$ (the initial signal is not too precise). 14. This distribution is consistent with the idea that there are a large number of buyers who are independently matched with sellers. The resulting distribution of the number of buyers matched with a seller is binomial. When the number of buyers and sellers is large, the binomial distribution is approximated by the Poisson distribution. 15. Another difference is that we do not have a separate entry stage. 16. Because of the Poisson distribution, $$e^{-\mu }$$ is both, the probability that a seller is matched with $$0$$ buyers and the probability that a buyer has no competitor. 17. Here and in the following, we use the generalized inverse of $$\beta$$, given by $$\beta ^{-1}\left( b\right) =\inf \left\{ \theta \in \left[ 0,1\right] |\beta \left( \theta \right) \geq b\right\}$$, where $$\beta ^{-1}\left( b\right) =1$$ if $$\beta \left( \theta \right) 0$$, there is some $$\bar{\delta}\left( \varepsilon \right)$$ such that for $$\delta \geq \bar{\delta}\left( \varepsilon \right)$$ there is a full-trade equilibrium with $$r_{0}=c+\varepsilon$$. 28. See Lemma 17 and its proof in the Online Appendix for the derivation of Equation (12). 29. Here, $$W\left( \theta _{+}^{B},\theta _{0}^{B}\right)$$ is the expected payoff of a buyer who behaves according to belief $$\theta _{+}^{B}$$ (the losing posterior), evaluated given $$\theta _{0}^{B}$$ (the tieing posterior). 30. The proof in the Appendix shows a stronger result, proving also the law-of-one-price: the realized transaction prices converge in distribution to a point in each state (to $$v$$ and $$p_{0}$$). 31. Otherwise, $$\lim D_{k}(\ell )/S_{k}(\ell )>0$$ would imply that the seller would surely trade in state $$\ell$$ even when he sets a reservation price of $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right) +\varepsilon$$ for some $$\varepsilon >0$$. Hence, setting a reservation price below $$\beta _{k}\left( 0\right)$$ would not be optimal so that $$\rho _{k}\left( 0\right) >\beta _{k}\left( 0\right)$$, a contradiction. 32. When the limit is competitive, $$p^{\ell }=c$$, there may be steady-state equilibria in which the sellers do not concede quickly (relative to $$\delta _{k}$$) in the limit. There is a possibility for an equilibrium in which the sellers set high reserve prices for a very long time, and the buyers bid close to $$p^{\ell }=c$$ for a long time as well. In this case, the sellers may not have incentives to accept those low bids because those offers are close to the sellers’ outside options, $$\lim V_{k}^{S}(0)+c=p^{\ell }=c$$ in the limit. 33. Similarly, in the model by Satterthwaite and Shneyerov (2008) without aggregate uncertainty, there are strategy profiles that are mutual best responses in which prices are too high because of the same problem. In that paper, the problem is solved by having the seller observe the bids before accepting and requiring sequentially rational acceptance decisions, which has the same implication as undominatedness here, namely, that sellers follow a reservation price strategy with $$r=\delta V^{S}+c$$. 34. See Section 4.3, where we discuss the sellers’ optimality of setting $$r_{0}$$. 35. The expected price conditional on $$b_{\left( 1\right) }\in \lbrack b_{1},b_{2}]$$ can be believed to be higher than $$b_{1}$$ but not lower. Similarly, the continuation payoff conditional on $$b_{\left( 1\right) }\in \lbrack b_{1},b_{2}]$$ may be believed to be lower than $$V^{S}(\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,[b_{1},b_{2}]))$$ but not higher. 36. It also implies that $$\theta _{0}^{S}(\theta,\left[ a,b\right] )$$ is increasing in $$a$$ and $$b$$, whenever $$\theta _{\left( 1\right) }\in \left[ a,b\right]$$ that has a positive probability. 37. This follows from the Bayesian consistency of the distribution of posterior beliefs in the stock; see also footnote 11. 38. To understand the distribution of market power, note the following. The winning bid is essentially a take-it-or-leave-it offer to the seller. Without aggregate uncertainty, the seller accepts any offer that makes him better off than waiting for the next period. This limits the market power of sellers. With aggregate uncertainty, however, “belief-threats” allow the seller to rationalize rejecting low offers and commit to a high reserve price. This essentially flips the order of moves and makes the seller the proposer. 39. This discussion of direct competition is somewhat reminiscient of the role of competition for partners in Felli and Roberts (2016). A similar $$\varepsilon$$-competition model is also studied as a special case in Lauermann (2013). 40. For example, the central arguments behind Proposition 4, namely, Lemmas 1 and 2, would extend immediately to this setting. 41. Search models for trade of an indivisible good—like ours—are useful for studying asset markets, but the assumed indivisibility is an important restriction that should be kept in mind. The advantage of an indivisible good model is its tractability. 42. Indeed, we show more: even for positive frictions, as long as they are not too large, there exists a natural class of full-trade equilibria that achieves a constrained efficient outcome, meaning that aggregate uncertainty and the war-of-attrition problem do not necessarily imply inefficiencies beyond those imposed by the decentralized meeting technology. 43. Indeed, in the previous section, we mentioned an empirical work of Bessembinder and Maxwell (2008) documenting the effect of the introduction of post-trade transparency. 44. A supplement with details is available on request. 45. A similar steady-state learning model with overlapping generations is Fudenberg and Levine (1993), albeit in a different literature. 46. Because, then the seller trades almost surely at the expected price $$p^{h}$$ in the limit as the mean trading price is $$p^{h}$$. 47. Formally, $$\lim \delta _{k}^{t_{k}}=1$$ is equivalent to $$\lim t_{k}(1-\delta _{k})=0$$. We need to have $$\lim \delta _{k}^{z_{k}}=1$$ or $$\lim z_{k}(1-\delta _{k})=0$$. Let $$\left( z_{k}(1-\delta _{k})\right) ^{2}=t_{k}(1-\delta _{k})$$, which clearly implies that $$\lim z_{k}(1-\delta _{k})=0$$ if $$\lim t_{k}(1-\delta _{k})=0.$$ Then $$\alpha _{k}^{2}t_{k}^{2}(1-\delta _{k})^{2}=t_{k}(1-\delta _{k})$$ or $$\alpha _{k}^{2}t_{k}(1-\delta _{k})=1$$. Then $$\lim t_{k}(1-\delta _{k})=0$$ implies that $$\lim \alpha _{k}=\infty$$, which then provides the appropriate construction. 48. This holds because if an arbitrary reserve price strategy trades at a price $$p$$ or above in a period, then strategy $$\Sigma (p)$$ trades at a price $$p$$ or above in that same period or before. 49. This argument assumes that the trading probability by period $$z_{k}$$ stays zero in the low state in the limit. But otherwise, a sure trading probability (over the entire lifetime) at price $$p$$ or above could be guaranteed in the low state. But then in both states a revenue of $$p$$ or above could be guaranteed and thus setting a reserve below $$p$$ and achieving a revenue of $$p^{h}$$ cannot be optimal in the high state. 50. Again, the argument assumes that the trading probability by period $$z_{k}$$ stays 0 in the low state in the limit. This assumption is without loss of generality, see the footnote 49 above for further discussion. 51. For example, with $$t_{k}=2$$,   qk(βk(z)|ℓ)<α≤  qk(βk(z)|ℓ)+(1−qk(βk(z)|ℓ))(1−δk)qk(βk(θ+k(z))|ℓ). 52. We explicitly verify that steady-state distributions satisfy this condition in Lemma 11 in the Online Appendix for the case of full-trade equilibria. 53. The mass of sellers present in the next period is $$1+\delta (S(w)-t(w))$$, which needs to be equal to $$S(w)$$ to reach a steady state. Therefore, $$1+\delta (S(w)-t(w))=S(w)$$ or $$S(w)=\frac{1-t(w)}{1-\delta}$$. 54. Note that,   limθ→0γS(θ|h)γS(θ|ℓ)=limθ→0ΓS(θ|h)ΓS(θ|ℓ)=0, and thus the fact that $$\frac{\gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is increasing in $$\theta$$ implies that $$\frac{\Gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |h\right)}{\Gamma ^{S}\left( \theta |\ell \right)}$$ is also increasing in $$\theta$$. © The Author 2017. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of The Review of Economic Studies Limited. This article is published and distributed under the terms of the Oxford University Press, Standard Journals Publication Model (https://academic.oup.com/journals/pages/about_us/legal/notices) TI - Learning and Price Discovery in a Search Market JO - The Review of Economic Studies DO - 10.1093/restud/rdx029 DA - 2018-04-01 UR - https://www.deepdyve.com/lp/oxford-university-press/learning-and-price-discovery-in-a-search-market-mCIGd6IMh9 SP - 1159 EP - 1192 VL - 85 IS - 2 DP - DeepDyve ER -